I. JNANA
Jnana is usually translated as
cognition. Cognition is the only thing that has intentionality or the property
of being directed at the world. It reveals objects in the world towards which
goal directed action can be initiated. It is of the nature of illumination like
a lamp and generates awareness in the subject of is objects. It is always used
in an episodic sense and never in a dispositional sense. The later job is done
by samskaras. Jnana is used to connote mental states like perception, memory,
introspection, assumption, doubt, belief etc. Jnana is divided into anubhava
and smriti. Anubhava is of the nature of presentation of its object while
smriti is recollection of a previous experience. Anubhava of an object makes an
impression in the mind of the subject and is stored there. When it is revived
due to diverse factors it leads to memory of its object. So anubhava is
presentational, of the form ‘I experience an object’, while memory is
derivative on anubhava for its content. Hence it is through anubhava that new
information is gained by the subject. Also it is anubhava which is true or
false judged by the way it reveals the world. Anubhava is divided into:
Perception, Inference, Verbal Testimony etc. depending on which modes of
awareness we regard as pramanas. Pramana-s are instruments of valid cognition.
Prama is valid cognition or knowledge.
II. PARATAH PRAMANYA
In virtue of which pramana leads to
prama is called pramanya. Pramanya refers to the abstract quality in virtue of
which a pramana has the status it does. The subject of knowledge is called
pramatri. Pramanya is translated as validity and is similar to the notion of
justification in western epistemology. Pramana is called the instrumental cause
of valid knowledge. An instrumental cause is that which has a vyapara
(operation) which culminates in producing the effect. For example the axe which
cuts the tree is the instrumental cause and the contact of axe with the tree is
the operation of the instrumental cause.
Mimamsakas argue that pramanya is
conferred intrinsically while Nyaya believes that pramanya is conferred
extrinsically. The former theory is known as svatah pramanya and the latter
paratah pramanya. Svatah pramanya vada holds that in order to explain the
validity of a cognition we need not appeal to anything outside the cognition.
For cognition is self-valid. The causes that produce cognition are also
productive of the cognition's validity. When we have a cognition we immediately
take it to be true and don’t entertain a doubt regarding its validity. Only
when we have a doubt do we make an attempt to determine whether a cognition is
valid or not. Thus there are two theories here, jnapti vada and utpatti vada.
The former which seeks to answer the question of production of valid knowledge
is utpatti vada and the latter which seeks to answer the question of grasping
valid knowledge is jnapti vada. The argument for utpatti vada is given by
Kumarila in (Slokavartika,
Codana 49-53) the interpretation of which is under dispute: "The validity
of all pramanas should be accepted as intrinsic for a capacity not already
existing by itself cannot be produced by anything else......” Cognition is born
with valid or invalid for we grasp its validity as it arises. It is not that
cognition arises first and then validity is conferred on it. For jnapti vada
the argument is if cognition’s validity is not conferred immediately then it
would not preclude doubt about its object and not lead to goal-oriented
activity. Kumarila also motivates his theory by pointing out that if a
cognition is not self valid then its validity will have to be determined by
another cognition, of this cognition we may also raise the question of its
validity and invalidity to adjudicate which we would need to appeal to a still
another cognition and the question of this cognition’s validity would similarly
arise and would have to be dealt with by appealing to another cognition and
this leads to an infinite regress. A cognition is a pramana if it is not
sublated by another cognition.
Nyaya motivates paratah pramanya vada
by pointing out that cognition is valid in virtue of being faithful or not to
the object it presents. Cognition has merits and demerits in virtue of which it
corresponds with its objects or not. So its validity is determined by adjudging
whether it corresponds with an object in the world, something which we cannot
decide merely on the basis of cognition. For suppose cognition presents us with
a shell in front of us. Merely on the basis of this we cannot decide whether
our cognition is true or not. When we go about and pick up the object, this
successful activity towards its object leads us to infer the validity of
cognition. This does not lead to an infinite regress because inquiry ends with
determination of an object and we do not doubt this certifying cognition and
hence we don’t need to decide its validity, for validity is determined only
when we have a doubt. Nyaya thus agrees with Mimamsaka that we never doubt our
cognitions but also hold that this condition is not sufficient for the truth of
the cognition. Rather this trust to our cognitions is due to habit and their
faithfulness in past but when doubt arises we do have to check the validity of
cognition by appealing to factors outside the cognition. We can also sometimes
entertain doubt about our cognition as soon as it arises. Seeing ground filled
with water in warm summer evokes surprise and doubt not certitude. Hence there
is not rule that as soon as cognition arises it leads to certitude about its
object. There are conditions where such a rule may not hold. This motivates
jnapti vada. For utpatti vada the argument is that causes of a cognition are
common to error and valid cognitions hence they cannot be the unique cause of
valid cognition. To escape this objection some Mimamsakas argue that there can
be no invalid cognition. Nyaya believes that we can have true and false
cognitions. But Mimamsakas point out that invalid cognition is only pseudo
cognition and not really cognition at all. Thus to settle this question both
sides have to debate on the possibility of invalid cognition.
III. NUMBER OF PRAMANAS
Nyaya believes there are four
pramanas – perception, inference, comparison and verbal testimony. Vaisesika
delete comparison and verbal testimony from the list as both can be assimilated
to inference. Buddhists likewise believe there are only two pramanas-
perception and inference. Mimamsakas believe there are six pramanas –
perception, inference, comparison, implication, non-apprehension and verbal
testimony. Implication (Arthapatti) leads to postulate a new state of affairs
to explain an otherwise incompatible set of propositions. For example if we
know that Devadatta is stout and is not eating anything in the morning, then we
postulate the state of affairs that Devadatta eats at night to explain these
seemingly incompatible propositions. Nyaya however take this to be inference.
Comparison (Upmana) is differently used in Nyaya and Mimamsa. In Nyaya it leads
to knowledge of new meanings of words. For Mimamsa it leads to knowledge of similarity.
Non-Apprehension (Anuplabdhi) leads to knowledge of absence. Nyaya believes
that absence is cognized through perception. When we see an empty floor where
we were expecting to see a pot, we recollect the pot and see the ground as
qualified by absence of a pot. There are four kinds of absence in Nyaya: a)
prior absence, this is the status of an object when it is absent before its
production b) posterior absence, this refers to an object that has been
destroyed c) absolute absence, this is absence of an object in a locus in all
three periods of time and d) mutual absence, this is absence of identity
between two objects. The entity negated is called the pratiyogin or
counterpositive of the negation, for example, when we say a pot is absent from
the floor, the pot is the pratiyogin or the counterpositive.
IV. PERCEPTION
Perception is defined as cognition
produced through sense organs. It is of two types: Indeterminate Perception and
Determinate Perception. In Indeterminate Perception sense organs merely make
contact with an object but this does not lead to determination of the object.
This happens at the second stage where we realize that the object in front of
me for example is really a table. Perceiving an object for first time, infant
and animal perception are examples of indeterminate perception. Determinate
Perception arises when an object is cognized in virtue of being the object it
is: To see a table qua its being a table. Here memory and sense organs both
need to operate. Perception of mental states is also included in this.
Pleasure, pain etc. are cognized. The common cause of all cognitions is contact
of the self – mind – sense organs – object.
V. INFERENCE
Inference or anumana in Nyaya is a
pramana, it leads to valid knowledge of some object based on another object
which acts as a sign or mark for the presence of the former object. The
previous knowledge of invariable concomitance between the sign and the
signified and the knowledge of their presence in a certain locus based on the
above said relation leads to anumana. To illustrate with the help of an
example, someone notices smoke on a mountain. Smoke reminds him of fire and
also that he has noticed their co-presence in a kitchen or a hearth and their
co-absence in a lake and thus he knows that smoke is invariably accompanied by
fire. Based on this knowledge of invariable concomitance (vyapti) between smoke
and fire, the person believes that the smoke on the mountain also must be
accompanied by fire and he concludes this must be the case. Here the Naiyayika
is not saying that psychologically we always go through this long process when
we infer something for a difference is made between inference for oneself and
for another. When we present our inferential knowledge we always do so in a
syllogistic form and the above description was of a way to convey one’s
inferential knowledge. The Nyaya syllogism consists of five steps:
1. Theory (Pratijna): The Mountain
possesses fire
2. Reason (hetu): because of smoke
3. Example (udharana): where there is
smoke there is fire as in a kitchen
4. Application (upanaya): This
Mountain similarly possesses smoke which is invariable concomitant with fire
5. Conclusion (nigamana): Therefore
the mountain possesses fire.
Here smoke is the hetu or the middle
term, fire is the sadhya or the major term and mountain is the paksha or the
minor term. The instances which have the co-presence of the smoke and fire is
the sapaksha and where such a relation is not found that is called the
vipaksha.
It should be noted that all examples
brought in an argument and counter argument to support an empirical
generalization must be acceptable to both the parties.
There are three different types of
inferences in Nyaya:
1. Kevalanvayi (only positive): when
the hetu and the sadhya have only a sapaksha but no vipaksha. For example: All
that is knowable is nameable. The pot is knowable and hence is nameable. Here
knowable and nameable pervade the whole world and hence there is no instance
where their co-absence may be found. (For Nyaya there is no instance where
knowability and nameability are absent).
2. Kevala Vyatireki (only negative):
here the hetu and sadhya have no positive instance of agreement in presence. An
example will suffice here: no non-soul is animate. All living beings are
animate. Therefore all living beings have souls. Here the hetu ‘animate’ is
said to be found only in living beings or beings possessing a soul and nowhere
else and hence no positive instance apart from the disputed case can be found.
Therefore the concomitance is established negatively, between absence of
possessing a soul and absence of ‘animate-ness’.
3. Anvaya Vyatireki (Agreement in
presence and absence): Here the hetu and sadhya are both positively and
negatively related to each other like in the mountain fire and smoke example.
Inference takes place always when
there is pervasion or vyapti between two objects which act as sign and the
signified. However vyapti may be of different types or degrees. When the
relation between the hetu and the sadhya is in an unfailing relation, here both
the objects may act as the sign and signified for each other. For example
something is sinful because it is prohibited in the Vedas and something is
prohibited in the Vedas because it is sinful. Then there may be an instance
where only one object forms the sign for another but not vica verse. For
example one may infer fire on the basis of smoke but not vica verse as fire
does not pervade smoke like in a red hot iron ball. Thirdly two objects may be
mutually exclusive for example the class of cows and the class of horses, where
the one is the other is not and hence there is a relation of exclusion between
them.
In Nyaya there are no fallacies but
blockers or preventers. The so called fallacies in Nyaya block the awareness or
cognition of an inference to arise or they themselves may be cognitions that
oppose the awareness of inference to arise. Mostly they are based on deviation
between the hetu and the sadhya, either there is some instance where the hetu
is and sadhya is not or their relation may be conditional. This brings us to
the theory of upadhi. Upadhi is something that pervades the sadhya but does not
pervade the hetu and hence blocks an inference. For example in the inference
mountain has smoke because it has fire, fuel is the upadhi, and it pervades
instances of smoke but not of fire for fire may be present in a red hot iron
ball.
Tarka is that which removes any doubt
about the invariable concomitance between two objects. It starts with an
assumption based on the denial of vyapti and shows how it leads to absurdities.
For example: If the soul was not eternal, then it may not experience the fruits
of past life and hence it is eternal.
VI. SHABDA
Verbal Testimony (Shabda) is knowledge
due to words spoken by a trustworthy person (apta). Expert opinion is included
in this. Vedas are valid for Nyaya because they are words of Ishvara who is a perfect
being and hence an (apta) trustworthy being. Mimamsakas however believe that
Vedas are eternal and not produced by any author not even Ishvara. Nyaya
believes that cognition produced by hearing the Vedas has to be determined as
true or false on basis on factors outside the cognition. Ishvara’s cognition is
perfect and hence can be appealed to determine the validity of Vedas.
Mimamsakas believe that it is enough if the cognition is not sublated by
another cognition for then it is self-valid and true. Hence no appeal to an
omniscient author is needed. Buddhists and Vaisesikas do not take Shabda to be a
pramana. For them it is a matter of inference.
First
of all verbal knowledge arises from verbal cognition i.e. it arises from
knowledge of the meaning of words and hence it is a mediate cognition. A
cognition is mediate when in order for a subject S to have cognition of Y; he
needs to cognize X which then acts as the instrumental cause (karana) of the
cognition of Y.
Instrumental
Cause (karana) is the unique cause which has an operation that leads to the
effect. For example in the felling of the tree the axe is the instrumental
cause and the contact of the axe with the tree is the operation (vyapara). Most
of the Nyaya philosophers from Raghunatha onward however take vyapara to be the
instrumental cause.
Perception
is regarded as immediate because there is no cognition of some X that acts as
the instrumental cause of the cognition of Y. In Inference cognition of vyapti
(invariable concomitance) is required for inferential cognition. In the case
of Verbal cognition it is knowledge of the meaning of the word. The meaning of
the word is established by will; human or divine. So a conventional relation
exists between the word and the referent of the word. There is no such relation
between the hetu (inferential sign) and sadhya (inferred entity) hence word
(Shabda) is a separate mode of cognition; different from both inference and
perception.
Now
the question arises how verbal testimony can be regarded as a source of
knowledge. The question is important because we seem to acquire a large chunk
of our information from verbal testimony. This is also to say that the
importance of testimony lies not in production of knowledge but in transmission
of knowledge. And here a serious problem arises: Being told that X is the case
does not produce knowledge of X for to gain knowledge of X one should look to
perception and inference. So knowledge gained second hand is not knowledge at
all. Hence verbal testimony should be reduced to perception or inference - a
distinct way of knowing. It could be argued that verbal testimony must be based
on the apprehension of trustworthiness of the speaker by the hearer. But how
can the hearer know the speaker is trustworthy except through verifying it on
the basis of perception and inference.
Against
this Nyaya philosophers urge that belief is implicated in the very act of
understanding (Shabda-Bodha) the meaning of words and in order to acquire a
true belief we need not have a justification for the belief. Moreover we need
to set conditions not only on the trustworthiness of the speaker but also on
the competence of the hearer. Someone gullible for instance would gulp every
falsehood spoken by someone but an intelligent hearer would take information
with a pinch of salt. And information would crystallize into knowledge only
when there is absence of doubt and the information is true. So in cases where
the speaker is qualified and credible and the information conveyed is believable
and true then there is no reason to deny knowledge arising from verbal
testimony.
Comments
Post a Comment