Skip to main content

An Essay On Social Sciences

 

..... Stop chatter and take to learning. This duty to keep in one's talk can be named an essential condition of all culture and all learning; one must begin by becoming capable of taking up the thoughts of others and of renouncing one's own fancies. It is usually said that the understanding is developed by questions, objections, answer etc.; in effect however it is not thus formed, but externally made. Man's inwardness is what is won and widened in true culture; he grows not poorer in thoughts or in quickness of mind by silently containing himself. He learns rather thereby ability to take up and acquires perception of the worthlessness of his own conceits and objections and as the perception of the worthlessness of such conceits grows he breaks himself of the having of them.

--------- HEGEL


I.                LOGICAL POSITIVISM

II.              HERMENEUTICS

III.            DIANOEMATICS

IV.            PHILOSOPHY OF SOCIAL SCIENCE

We shall look at two schools of thought – Logical Positivism and Hermeneutics. The first tries to assimilate social science explanations to the methods followed in natural sciences. The second tries to argue for autonomy of social sciences. The key is to understand what constitutes an explanation and what should be the goal or object of study for human sciences. Taking our lessons from both I shall attempt to sketch a philosophy of social science.

LOGICAL POSITIVISM

In his paper ‘The Functions of General Laws in History’, Carl Hempel makes an argument that the methods followed in a human science like history is akin to the methods of natural science and that it has to be so in order to be counted as a science at all. But what is the nature of explanation within natural science? To quote Hempel:

“The explanation of the occurrence of an event of some specific kind E at a certain place and time consists, as it is usually expressed, in indicating the causes or determining factors of E. Now the assertion that a set of events-say, of the kinds C1, C., . . ., C.- have caused the event to be explained, amounts to the statement that, according to certain general laws, a set of events of the kinds mentioned is regularly accompanied by an event of kind E. Thus, the scientific explanation of the event in question consists of (1) a set of statements asserting the occurrence of certain events C1, . . . C, at certain times and places, (2) a set of universal hypotheses, such that (a) the statements of both groups are reasonably well con-firmed by empirical evidence, (b) from the two groups of statements the sentence asserting the occurrence of event E can be logically deduced. In a physical explanation, group (1) would describe the initial and boundary conditions for the occurrence of the final event; generally, we shall say that group (1) states the determining conditions for the event to be explained, while group (2) contains the general laws on which the explanation is based; they imply the statement that whenever events of the kind described in the first group occur, an event of the kind to be explained will take place.”

According to Hempel there is only a pragmatic distinction between explanation and prediction. Hence to explain is to discover a general law that allows us to make accurate predictions that are capable of being verified. General Laws are causal laws where causality is understood in terms of a regular relation between two entities or events. Explanations may be probabilistic; one may form an explanation sketch to be filled out by future empirical research. Science is a body of statements where one statement specifies the general law from which other statements are deduced by rules of formal logic. The deduction is important for without it explanations will not proceed and we would be unable to distinguish an explanation from a lucky guess. Psuedo-explanations are excluded on the grounds that they lack empirical / cognitive content (i.e. anything that is thinkable has an empirical content). Hence explanations in terms of entelechies, God etc. are ruled out. But this would prove too much for we shall not be able to infer theoretical entities like protons, electron etc. which are unobservable. They are brought within the purview of science via their empirical consequences. The factual content of science distinguishes it from moral and aesthetic statements which lack cognitive content and are really expressions of human sentiments.

What however is the reason to apply such a method in case of a humanistic science like history? Hempel says:

“Historical explanation, too, aims at showing that the event in question was not "a matter of chance," but was to be expected in view of certain antecedent or simultaneous conditions. The expectation referred to is not prophecy or divination, but rational scientific anticipation which rests on the assumption of general laws.”

Hempel further tries to defuse the impression that there is a gap between theory and practice in this case for historians seldom resort to general laws to explain historical events. His grounds are that the explanation of explanation that he has sketched applies implicitly (universal hypothetical laws of social psychology or other disciplines are generally assumed) even in case of historical explanation and is able to distinguish pseudo-explanations in history from bona fide ones:

“All of them rest on the assumption of universal hypotheses which connect certain characteristics of individual or group life with others; but in many cases, the content of the hypotheses which are tacitly assumed in a given explanation can be reconstructed only quite approximately.”

Incomplete explanations are no bar for they are really explanation sketches capable of being filled out in time. A historian may resort to empathetic understanding of history but this may be an aid to a historian it does not constitute an explanation. We need to distinguish between the methods of discovery and the methods of justification. Justification rests on a set of statements where the explanandum is deduced from a general law which is the explanans.

The demarcation between science and non-science is like setting boundaries between rational and irrational. The reason is that rationality depends on conceptual content of thought and logical positivists restrict conceptual content to what can be experienced via our senses. Such restriction of applicability of contents requires an epistemological and psychological theory and such has been provided by Carnap in his Aufbau. Any statement that is devoid of empirical consequences lacks cognitive content. A theory of concept seeks to understand (i) what a concept is or what is that is thought, (ii) the genesis or the source of the concept (this is distinct from the question of how we come to acquire a concept) (iii) the objective validity of the concept. What are the boundaries of a concept and why does it have those boundaries? To answer these questions we need to go beyond empirical descriptions of conceptual thinking because empirical sciences presuppose the validity of their concepts. Logical Positivism takes conceptual clarification to be their only aim as philosophers so that scientists can continue with their work without entertaining any philosophical scruples. But given the role of concepts in scientific explanation why should we think there is a gap between scientific understanding and scientific explanation? Any justification depends on the correct application of concepts and the legitimate bounds of a concept. We cannot arrive at the proper rules of deduction for a formal logic without having an understanding of what concepts are. Otherwise such a logic would be in Husserl’s words a logic that does not understand itself. So to understand science itself one needs to understand the relation between a subject and an object of knowledge and the very possibility of knowledge. Logical positivism should be understood as a theory of concepts where an attempt is made to restrict the validity and utility of our concepts to an empirical domain precluding any attempt to ground concepts in a First Principle that would take us outside the natural realm. Hence the divorce between understanding and explanation that is being sought after by Hempel et al amounts to an inconsistency.

There are a number of problems however with this neat picture of scientific explanation:

1. The analysis of causality in terms of regularity is questionable. We may adduce here one such counter-example given by Henry Kyburg cited in Wesley Salmon’s Four Decades of Scientific Explanation:

“A sample of table salt has been placed in water and it has dissolved. Why? Because a person wearing a funny hat mumbled some non-sense syllables and waved a hand over it - i.e. cast a dissolving spell upon it. The explanation offered for the fact that it dissolved is that it was hexed and all hexed samples of table salt dissolve when placed in water. In this example it is not being supposed that any actual magic occurs. All hexed table salt is water soluble because table salt is water soluble. This example fulfils the requirements for D-N explanation, but it manifestly fails to be a bona fide explanation.”

Such counter-examples may be indefinitely multiplied. Whatever may be the correct way to understand causation it seems Hempel has put the cart before the horse. Laws do not constitute an explanation they themselves are in need of an explanation. Instead of explaining causality in terms of laws one should understand laws in terms of causation. By taking a law to be simply a description of a regular sequence Hempel ignores the context of scientific inquiry. One needs to understand why two things are always constantly conjoined together and what the relation between the two is. This is what propels a scientific inquiry and calls for a scientific explanation. To explain is to give a reason and if to give a reason is to cite a cause then a better account of causality is needed.

 

2. The exclusion of entelechies and like entities is not neat for as we have seen it would throw out theoretical entities from the sphere of scientific explanation. And if noting empirical consequences is a basis of inferring unobservable entities then it is not clear why the same courtesy should not be extended to metaphysical entities like entelechies. The analysis of meaning in terms of empirical or verifiable content is not so clean and does not play the regulative role that logical positivists intend it to.

 

3. It has been pointed out that the source of rationality of a science lies within its concepts. The application of these concepts within scientific practice depends on a method. But when logical positivists insist on uniformity of method within natural and social sciences they seek to reverse the priority of concepts to a method. This is necessary for we cannot go outside science to determine the validity of science. All our standards for valid thought come within the realm of scientific practice. Hence it is the scientific method that has the priority and our theory of concepts depend on that and hence method is the source of rationality of a science (cf. Neurath’s Boat, Schlick et al denied their foundationalism was of the traditional type). The scientific method itself is what demarcates the rational from the irrational and science from pseudo-science. But I shall argue that the source of rationality of a science cannot lie within the method. To do that I shall have to sketch a picture of human rationality.

Any successful action requires conception and execution. First is the ability to see - to grasp the fundamentals of the situation and then adapt action to circumstance. Methods are mechanical procedures to execute a vision - they themselves do not provide a vision. Their inflexibility is their virtue for they require action to follow a basic set of rules and circumstances in which those rules can be properly implemented. They require a constancy in circumstances and cannot adapt to change in circumstances. Without conception methods cannot adapt to situations. It is the prerogative of vision to decide which methods would be best to use in certain circumstances - by setting a goal and a strategy to achieve that goal it gives action a direction which it cannot provide itself by itself. Methods do not tell us which goal is worthy of achievement - what value we should attach to it; what value we should use to evaluate it. They also do not tell us which strategy we should adopt to achieve that goal - for there may be innumerable ways to achieve a goal – not all equally effective - that assessment would depend on the circumstances - the end, the means to achieve that end, current situation and the likely consequences of the action. And if there are new facts that alter the circumstances then the methods need to be varied to achieve the intended result. But methods can work only when we assign to them a task - they cannot set a task for themselves. Selection of method requires intelligence to assess a situation, set a goal and the means by which that goal should be achieved. If selection of method itself requires a method then the selection of that method would require using another method about which the same problem would arise. The regress terminates in an intelligence that is able to see which method should be the most appropriate to use. A method is like a tool - its proper use depends on an intelligent agent. The fashioning of the tool itself requires an intelligent agent.

Philosophy is the science of wisdom and wisdom is the ability to grasp principles. The use of the word ‘principles’ in this case indicates an understanding that is able to grasp the ‘why’ of things. Comprehension of principles requires insight which is not mechanical - for there cannot be a method to choose a method. Hence insight into principles is needed. Every effective way of thinking requires generality of thought to be adapted to the individuality of particular situations. First thought abstracts from the particulars of a situation to arrive at principles that remain constant through situations (for e.g. you can see in the case of laws of physics). It is the job of principles to explain why things are the way they are. Principles capture the rational structure inherent in situations - making them intelligible to thought - allowing foresight to anticipate the unknown on the basis of known. Because these principles are abstract accuracy cannot be guaranteed but they can minimize the risk of inaccuracy and they allow us to assess how far short we are of our ideal. They come under the domain of theoretical rationality as opposed to practical and procedural rationality i.e. they are concerned with truth - determination of the way things are and their rationalization. Practical rationality steps in when we are concerned with application of these principles - which is different from procedural rationality for we are not yet concerned with execution. We are concerned with how a principle ought to be applied to particular situations and again there are innumerable ways not equally good or valid for all situations by which the principles be applied to particulars of a situation and even here we need to select which one is the most salient. Principles here are like ‘ideals’ they cannot be completely applied to particulars of a situation for if they could then they would cease being ‘ideals’, but they can serve as a benchmark - that provide us a standard of evaluation to judge our actions. The closer we are in spirit to the principles the better. Only after a course of action has been decided does procedural rationality come in - which requires speed of action, physical energy, practice and discipline and like virtues. Procedural rationality is about skills - it requires blind execution of rules or a method you have acquired via practice which has become habit. But it is only a part of human rationality not the entire thing and is empty without theoretical and practical rationality to which it ought to be subordinated for that is its proper place and each thing is valid only within its proper sphere. 

The source of rationality of a method lies in the intelligence that selects it and hence a theory of concepts that looks to understand the relation of a subject and object of knowledge should not be restricted to following a rule or a method blindly. We can make four more points here. First any human endeavour requires taking values seriously. It is only by subordinating our actions to certain values that we can have the ability to decide the validity of our actions. In case of cognitive enterprises Truth is such a value. Second, this shows that the exclusion of moral and aesthetic cognition on grounds of lack of factual content is not valid. For normativity is an essential feature of any human endeavour and cognitive endeavours are not free from normative considerations themselves. And these normative considerations and not factuality are what determine whether an activity is rational or irrational. Third, this undercuts the assimilation of history to method of natural sciences on grounds of uniformity of method. Fourth, the task of philosophy cannot consist only in conceptual analysis for philosophy needs to understand what constitutes an adequate or successful analysis and where do these norms come from. Kant pointed out that every analysis is preceded by a synthesis. First we have a vague conception of the whole, then via analysis we dissect it into parts giving our attention to them and then conclude with a more distinct synthesis. Simply to build a mathematical simulation model is not to understand something for initial indistinct understanding will be carried forward to the translation of the concept in a mathematical model. Far from improving our understanding it would be as misinformed as our initial defunct understanding. This is revealed in economic theories of perfect competition in theoretical markets and rational choice theory of agents which assumes as it were that human beings are like Robinson Crusoe in a lone island. The phenomenon of rational irrationality shows that it is a mistake to consider an individual in isolation from the system and the need to consider his choices as embedded within the system itself. The situation is much different in real life. Economists building such theories were living in mathematical paradises and their theories were simply mathematically elegant but lacking empirical application. Hence we see the switch to behavioural economics in recent times in study of economics.

The fear that on this picture of human rationality empirical facts would lose currency in favour of metaphysical principles and that we would be adjusting facts for theories rather than theories for facts is unwarranted. The point of a principle is to explain a fact. Facts can be understood only via principles for facts do not explain themselves - principles need to be appealed to in order to explain facts. Locke seeks to reverse the priority. His reason is in a way understandable. In the age in which he lived we find an extreme forms of rationalism prevalent. For Aristotle study of empirical facts was necessary - for principles are found in the facts because they instantiate a Form or Essence - that explain why certain facts are the way they are. To know a thing in essence is to know it truly. An explanation has to hold true of an object in its essence. Consider a doctor who can recognize the disease by its symptoms versus a doctor who knows the disease in essence. The former can treat the symptoms but the latter has a greater chance to find a cure. Aristotle begins with common experience or common opinions and via a dialectic whereby considering different perspectives on a topic he seeks to arrive at the correct way of thinking about something. But beginning with Descartes we find a sharp division between facts and principles thereby giving priority to principles over human experience. If the latter is in conflict with the former - so much the worse for the latter and Principles are justified purely by intuition. Clearly Reason is credited with way too much power in order to justify dogmas of religion. And we are asked to be more certain that we should be about our conclusions. Without considering diverse opinions or diverse perspectives on an issue - being certain amounts to being dogmatic. And it is this dogmatism Locke was opposed to.

But like his opponents he too separates facts from principles. As often happens two mutually opposed options seem to be mutually exclusive. But the mutual opposition is based on a substantial agreement which in this case is the separation of fact and principle - whereas Rationalists like Descartes clear away experience in favour of Reason - empiricists like Locke go to the other extreme and clear away Reason in favour of experience. But what we need is a balance between the two. Without facts principles cannot be applied and without principles facts cannot be explained. Science cannot replace philosophy because by itself it cannot yield scientific understanding. We need to distinguish between science as a skill and science as knowledge. As a skill it is a tool for prediction of phenomena but as knowledge it demands explanation of facts. And to explain what an explanation is we need philosophy.

 

4. We have seen that law-like regularity and uniformity of methods fails to be a consideration for assimilating human sciences to natural sciences. Nancy Cartwright in her ‘How the Laws of Physics Lie’ shows that laws are really idealizations based on experiments conducted within controlled laboratory conditions. Even within natural sciences laws do not play an essential role the way logical positivists would have us believe. Neither are any strict laws discoverable in social phenomena given its complexity nor can be make any idealizations based on controlled laboratory conditions. Even then human sciences need not cease to be rational as the preceding considerations show.

We have resisted the subsumption of human sciences to natural sciences but now we need to resist another extreme that claims autonomy of social sciences from natural sciences on grounds that the nature of explanation markedly differs in the two cases. I support the autonomy case but on different grounds.

 

HERMENEUTICS

Gadamer’s Hermeneutics is about experience of Truth and this experience occurs in an aesthetic consciousness. Human sciences differ from natural ones since they are about culture. In a lecture at a 1995 conference Gadamer says:

“To be cultured is obviously to cultivate a particular form of distance. Hegel already wondered what constituted a cultured person. The cultured person is the one who is ready to admit as plausible (literally, to value) the thoughts of others. I say that we discover here a remarkable description of the uncultured person: it is typically the person who maintains in all possible circumstances and all possible contexts and with a dictatorial assurance whatever wisdom he has picked up by chance. On the contrary, to leave something undecided is what constitutes the essence of those who can ask questions. The person who is not equal to recognising his own ignorance and, for that reason, to keeping the open character of some decisions precisely in order to find the right solution, will never be what is called a cultured person. The cultured person is not the one who displays superior knowledge, but only the one who, to take an expression from Socrates, has not forgotten the knowledge of his ignorance.”

 

Jean Grondin comments on this (in his Philosophy Of Gadamer Tr. Kathyrn Plant):

“Such is the ideal of culture which has always been that of the human sciences, and indeed that of the human condition. It is a matter of knowing limitations and humility. The essential is not to store items of knowledge, but to realize one’s own ignorance when in contact with historical, literary, linguistic and philosophical knowledge. By this hold of self-awareness, one is raised to a certain universality. Gadamer was inspired here by Hegel’s pedagogic texts: if the essence of culture or of formation is to raise us to universality, it is because we are taught to open ourselves to other approaches, to other and more general perspectives.18 To be able to adopt a distance with respect to particularity, beginning with one’s own, is what constitutes essential knowledge, that of culture and formation, because it transforms us.”

 

How does culture transform an individual? This is the key question. The answer is that the more we learn the more we become aware of our ignorance. But learning takes place through our openness to different perspectives. Learning requires humility and it makes us aware of our finitude. It is not solely about the object known but also about the impact learning has for an individual. This is what distinguishes human sciences from natural sciences. In the latter our sole concern is the fact and the one who looks for facts is not in any way transformed by finding facts. Hence natural science is not a cultural pursuit.

 

Jean Grondin elaborates on this point:

 

“What is formed here is thus a capacity for judgement, or taste, but this concept no longer has anything other than a trivially aesthetic sense….. Gadamer already associates the nature of this historical knowledge with the Aristotelian idea of practical wisdom. Several crucial elements are common to these types of knowledge: as is indicated by the Aristotelian distinction between the practical and the technical, it is not a matter of learning rules, but of a wisdom in life; further, this virtue is not taught, it is formed or cultivated; this wisdom has no particular content and is not dogmatic, but rather consists of a capacity to adapt itself to particular situations. It is a matter of knowledge, or better, of a sense, or better, of a common sense since it allows us to transcend particularity. Science seeks the universal in the form of laws, but we must recognize, with Aristotle, that we are here talking about knowledge of another sort.”

 

But example how is this formation of transformation of the individual effected? It is not possible by cultivation of a method because it is not a technical achievement. This transformation occurs in understanding. Understanding is not acquisition of knowledge or conceptual interpretation. It is an event and it has to be understood via aesthetic experience. Aesthetics has been taken to be a matter of taste and hence subjective as opposed to the objective methods of science. But this way of thinking needs to be challenged. An aesthetic experience reveals to us the truth in art; through aesthetics we can arrive at a perspective of Truth which is more important than the narrow perspective ingrained within us by practice of natural sciences. Experience of art opens us to Being or Essence or Meaning of the work of art. In Heideggerian language this disclosure of Being is Truth. Gadamer takes his cue from allegories often ignored in aesthetics. The reason is that an allegory conveys something or represents something else whereas in aesthetics we are used to take art as an object in itself. An allegory on the other hands reveals or presents (Darstellung) something. It is this presentation of the Being of a being or the meaning of a work of art that is the experience of Truth. It reveals Being to us and hence Gadamer talks about the ontology of art. Truth is not a prerogative of cognitive endeavours. A very weak conception of Truth informs such endeavours. In this case the experience of Truth transforms an individual; as Grondin says reality is transfigured because rediscovered. Art mediates this experience which leads to recognition (Mimesis) of Being. This is the key to aesthetic consciousness which brings us to Truth; the Truth we aspire in Human Sciences or in cultural pursuits.

 

But how and why does such an event or moment of understanding occur? We do not know how understanding occurs but we know that it does and it has an effect on the individual. But the nature of this understanding has to be understood clearly. It is not an a-temporal understanding because we are not a-temporal beings. We are finite and temporal beings and a historical consciousness of ourselves has to be temporal and would reveal our finitude. A finite individual is embedded in certain temporal circumstances from which he cannot free himself. His social practices have an effect on his capability to think. He begins with a certain prejudice-structure but this does not hamper understanding on the contrary it facilitates it. A text just like an individual interpreter has its own temporal horizon. In interpreting a text an individual comes to it with questions pertinent to his own temporal horizon but the answers to which he can get only via an openness towards the horizon of the text. This openness leads to an understanding of the text where there is as it were an integration between two different horizons. The meaning of the text is appropriated within the horizon of the interpreter. This openness to an alternative perspective is the experience of Truth.

 

There is much to admire in this elegant picture of human sciences. But it is also vitiated by certain serious problems:

 

1. Truth and falsehood, knowledge and ignorance always come to us in pairs. We cannot have one without the other. Does the experience of Truth allow us to distinguish between Truth and Falsehood? Does the experience determine for us the correct interpretation of the text? If it does not what Truth is exactly revealed to us? Is it possible for different people living in different horizons to have the same experience of Truth? Can dialogues and interpretations converge on a single fact of the matter? If not then is not the entire exercise (or game as Gadamer would call it) pointless? If a reason given for one interpretation is in principle not stronger than another then we do not have Truth but rather end in a nihilism. The pursuit of Truth puts us under certain normative obligations or standards to meet. The point of norms is the ability to distinguish between Truth and Falsehood. But without being able to discriminate between the two our experience of Truth is pointless; Truth loses its meaning here because we cannot distinguish Truth from falsehood.

 

2. What exactly is revealed to us in this experience of Truth? If the answer is Being then can we ask what is Being? For Gadamer like Heidegger we cannot ask what is Being because Being is not a something. But in what way do we distinguish between Being and Nothing in this case? What makes an experience an experience of Being? The point is not that we should be able to articulate what we experience. The point is that an experience cannot be called recognitive or one that leads to understanding and ineffable at the same time. What have we understood and is there anything apart from a feeling that tells us that we have truly understood it. What meaning is revealed? If it is something we can recognize then it is capable of being grasped by us or is rational or intelligible. If it is ineffable then how do we distinguish between an understanding of something and an understanding of nothing which is really no understanding at all? Stanley Rosen criticizing Heidegger’s Ereignis (E-Event) in his The Question of Being makes this pertinent point:

 

“Either the E-Event is thinkable or it is not. If it is thinkable, then there must be some content to our thoughts, in which case the E-Event is though 'as' such and such, which is directly contrary to Heidegger's intentions. On the other hand, if we are to avoid 'thinking' the E-Event in any sense that connotes content peculiar to E-event, since there is nothing in Being 'about' which to think we are left with the sole alternative of thinking about what eventuates, that is, about beings.”

 

The point can be made with the same force against Gadamer. If there is no such thing as Truth then expectation would always lead to reality. But since there is distinction between appearance and reality our expectations can be frustrated. However the opposite picture seems to hold in Gadamer as a consequence of his views.

 

3. We have seen that Truth ceases to play any regulative role in Gadamer’s hermeneutics. However to think that Truth plays such a regulative role is not instrumentalist thinking. Knowledge deployed for practical purposes need not be pursued for those same reasons. But there is nothing wrong in application of knowledge to everyday life. Gadamer and Heidegger too wish to effect a transformation of the individual. This does not however make their views on understanding instrumentalist.

 

4. Which prejudices facilitate understand and which ones are obstacles? How do we make this normative assessment? Gadamer is not blind to this problem, he says that the:

 

“….. Central question, the fundamental question from the point of view of the theory of knowledge can be formulated in this way: on what is to be founded the legitimacy of prejudices? What distinguishes legitimate prejudices from all those innumerable ones which critical reason must incontestably overcome?”

 

Grondin elaborates:

 

“An important question, but one that hides an even more important paradox: if we see in prejudices the conditions of understanding, do we not, by the very fact of the same confirmation, cut ourselves off from the things themselves?”

 

And again:

 

“………in Truth and Method at least, has Gadamer clearly succeeded in “going beyond epistemological interrogation” in hermeneutics when he still gives such an epistemological emphasis to the problem of the truth of prejudices? Does the concept of truth that he tries to elaborate from the experience of art not try to frustrate too epistemological, too instrumental an understanding of truth?”

 

Gadamer never gives an adequate solution to the problem and Grondin underestimates it seeing it as just a minor difficulty.

 

5. Can Truth be temporal? A-temporality seems essential to Truth. But then take the discovery of the fore-structure of human being and his consequence finitude. Is that not an a-temporal Truth? Truth is not a value that is subject to human prejudices and social practices. If rational and moral standards originate in social rules then our very ability to think morally depends on attestation by social standards. How would then we be able to evaluate social standards themselves? What would we test them against? More standards? Where would they come from? How could we make a statement like JK did that social morality is immorality. Would we be constrained to accept slavery because social conventions favour it? If we do then there would be no way out for a victim of tyranny because for the latter anything goes. The same would apply to rational standards. I think Gadamer destroys Truth as a value which is to say that instead of his explicit promise to provide us with an account of experience of Truth in Art he has really destroyed Truth itself.

 

6. Can a change in consciousness be effected by a fusion of horizons? For Gadamer the penetration effected between two different horizons affects the underlying structure of our fore-knowledge and thus causes change. It is the passivity of understanding that effects a change within us. While it is known since Hume pronounced reason to be a slave of passions yet without rational control a change within a prejudicial structure is not possible; not simply given the passivity of understanding. This is not to deny what can be expressed in Niccolai Hartmann’s words: “Emotional awareness of reality lies at the bottom of all cognitive activity.” Character can be seen as a ground for feelings and emotions that predispose us towards certain values. Acquisition of knowledge does not require merely intellectual skills but also a feel for the Truth that motivates the search for the Truth. The value system of the individual counts but feelings and reason have to be co-ordinated together to effect a change.

 

Also it will be useful to distinguish between prejudices and pre-judgements. For instance if I am a teacher and I have a low opinion of a student and someday I receive an essay written by that student and I read it to find to my astonishment that it is actually good. Not too good for then I should suspect plagiarism but good in a way that reflects that the student has worked hard and made some progress. If in such a case I would still give him less marks to be consistent with my previous judgement then I am prejudiced. But if I change my opinion and give him marks he deserves then my previous judgement does not have a hold on me to an extent that it hinders my present judgement and hence that is not a case of prejudice. Pre-formed judgements can be an aid in an inquiry as they help in orienting us in a particular direction. For example a cop has to begin somewhere with a murder investigation. Certain pre-judgements about the case assist in giving his investigation a direction. Perhaps people he suspected turn out to be innocent but he has to get a start and adapt according to the situation. Ultimately change is effected only by adjusting our actions in light of our experiences and our comprehension of those experiences and our ability to adapt to different situations and mitigate the influence of those prejudices that hamper our ability to respond to different situations or challenges. We see and act but Gadamer’s seeing causes an unbridgeable chasm to develop between seeing and acting in fear of epistemological or instrumental readings of understanding creeping in.

 

DIANOEMATICS

This is a term used by the French Philosopher and Historian Martial Gueroult to denote an inquiry into the philosophical value of history of philosophy. It is an inquiry akin to Kant’s Transcendental Deduction into the possibility of history of philosophy as a discipline. In his paper ‘The History of Philosophy as a Philosophical Problem’, Gueroult frames the aporia for history of philosophy in this way:

“On the one hand, the problem arises necessarily from the moment one considers the definition that all philosophy gives of itself: philosophy presents itself as an expression of the truth and as something timeless and eternally valid, since truth is by definition timeless. And on the other hand it arises from the moment one considers the fact that philosophy also presents itself as a series of doctrines succeeding one another in time and swallowing up one another in the completed past. As something past, philosophy can without difficulty be the object of history, which is defined as the effort to exhume all that is past. But as past that is completed, past that is surpassed, it seems to exclude the history of philosophy. For is it not, by virtue of being completely past, not truth, since truth does not pass? Philosophy could not therefore be the object of a history of philosophy since, being without truth, it would be without philosophy. History is only possible by virtue of a value which raises its material to the dignity of a possible object for history. But if the past of philosophy is, thanks to being historically past, deprived of the value (truth) which would justify it as an object worthy of history, the history of philosophy is philosophically illegitimate. Hence this problem: how to reconcile the historicity of philosophy with the philosophical truth of all philosophy. And then this: how to define, correlatively, the concept of philosophical truth.”

And,

“Can philosophy, which is always expressed through a doctrine given as truth, and thus as timeless, allow itself to be submitted to history, which reduces all philosophy to an event which passes, thus to something without truth (since truth never passes)? Reciprocally, can history, which reduces all philosophy to a passing event, admit a philosophy which always claims to be a truth, which in itself escapes the vicissitudes and laws of history, even though it came into being at a certain moment of history?”

The formulation of the problem sees philosophy as Truth and hence timeless and thus philosophy can either be past in which case it would not be philosophy or Truth in which case its historicity is an accident.

Further ahead in the paper Gueroult enters into a very instructive discussion regarding why a philosopher can never be free of history of philosophy (contra Descartes) and how history of philosophy differs from history of science. Gueroult argues against reduction of philosophy to history on grounds that philosophy is a science – a body of knowledge held together by internal reasons that make a claim to Truth:

“Philosophy emerges from the necessary sequence of notions. It presents the character of unity and rational interiority. The history of philosophy, on the contrary, brings doc trines, notions, and concepts from the outside, as facts. It is therefore the negation of philosophy which, far from being the passive acceptance of ready-made solutions or the empirical knowledge of an external giver, is knowledge through internal reason. Philosophy, by definition, challenges any history because it is science grasped in its fundamental form as the necessary sequence of evident truths which owe their certainty to this evidence, and their usefulness to this certainty. History, the knowledge of facts, a knowledge exterior to its object, can never be deduced from internal reasons; accordingly it is uncertain and consequently useless. Even if it reaches certainty about a fact, this knowledge of contingent and single facts never leads to a science properly speaking, which is always necessary and universal. To wish to subject philosophy to history under these conditions is to bring the corruption of philosophy to its highest point.”

The history of philosophy is a history of doctrines or systems succeeding one another while at the same time making claims to a timeless and universally valid Truth. A historian of philosophy unlike a historian of science is not free of the past for previous doctrines remain with him as “a collection of latent philosophical possibilities offered for meditation, from which the philosopher can indefinitely draw his inspirations.” Thus on the one hand history of philosophy professes to be a temporal phenomenon to be studied by a historian like any other piece of history. Yet a philosophy presents to a historian as an eternally present system that is still living and from which still philosophical truths may be drawn. Faced with such contrary tendencies the historian has two choices. The first and the one Gadamer has taken is:

“Considering philosophies not as eternal truths, but as temporal and contingent events, the historian will explain them historically, like other historical events, by the conjunction of individual and social factors, milieu, time, etc. He will not explain them by the connection between the thoughts and that absolute of truth which legitimize them in their own terms. Taken to the limit, this tendency leads to treating the details of contents and the techniques used to establish and demonstrate doctrines as illusory epiphenomena, and to reducing them to a small number of fundamental themes, which would be the only ones to which historico-psychological causes are applicable. One will not go deeper into the mysteries of the system, just as classical psychopathology does not trouble itself to note the details of a raving man's visions, rather contenting itself with characterizing them in order to diagnose the nosological entity. Similarly, reduced to the state of symptoms of psychological or social complexes, philosophies will be stripped of the details of their insights and summed up in terms of their outlines which reveal the underlying tendencies of a man and of a society. The psychological and sociological will ultimately be substituted for the philosophical in establishing the essential of a history of philosophy which would no longer be philosophical.”

But the historian of philosophy can never really go that far because he finds himself torn by an equally forceful philosophical tendency. By substituting a psychological or social explanation for a philosophical one he essentially destroys his object of study. The desire for explanation limits the tendency to explain a philosophy via external reasons alone and makes one see the internal point of view of a philosophical doctrine.

The second tendency is one where history is sacrificed for philosophy. History as Gueroult points, out requires a sense of the past and is directed towards historical truth and not philosophical truth. Gueroult points out that this tendency marks itself in polemics where the existence of the past in not understood and needs to be got rid of. Philosophy is the eternal truth and can have no history. Or else past philosophers may be seen as progressing towards the one true point of view which it is the prerogative of the present to propagate (Gueroult agrees with Dilthey that this is the turn that study of history of philosophy took with the advent of Christianity and the excommunication of tradition in name of philosophy peaked within the Cartesian System. The polemical tendency on the other hand is found in Aristotle).     

Gueroult finds both alternatives distasteful and looks for a third. There are however certain things that any alternative should accommodate: a) Every philosophy though in a way is a break from the past is nevertheless incapable of completely separating itself from the past, b) unlike a scientist a philosopher needs history of philosophy to get a grasp of philosophy, c) even though historical and scientific interests can be separated in philosophy the two are ‘intimately intermingled’, d) historical truth and philosophical truth cannot be dissociated unlike in other sciences.

The historian of philosophy is motivated to study history of philosophy for not simply a historical value but for a philosophical value. This philosophical value has to be Truth. But this Truth is not representative Truth or scientific Truth that divides different philosophies and is a bone of contention between them but an internal truth of inner reasons that unites a body of doctrine. Like Gadamer Gueroult too invokes aesthetic sense to explicate his notion of an inner truth of doctrines:

“Philosophies stand as monuments of thought having their own value, which is impervious to history; they are as much eternal objects for meditation as artistic monuments are eternal objects for contemplation and emotion. Their paradoxical permanence does not lie in their representative truth, defined as adaequatio rei et intellectus; indeed on the contrary it is through it that they appear to be frail, contradicting one another, and running counter to the science of today and tomorrow. It is due to their intrinsic truth, that is, to the concept that they enclose something real (sui generis), born of their systematic and architectonic constitution. Now, what constitutes the immortal substance of all works of arts is precisely an intrinsic truth, veritas in re, which is heterogeneous with all truths of judgment.”

But there is an important distinction between art and philosophy that should not be overlooked:

“Such a parallelism ought not nevertheless to mask one essential difference. Contrary to what takes place in art, philosophies do not take it upon themselves to build self-sufficient monuments, but to attain, as in science, to a truth of judgment, to resolve a problem by means of a theory. In this they are closer to science and further from works of art. To be sure, this confirms that their permanence is based on an intrinsic value (veritas in re), not on a truth of judg ment (veritas in repraesentando), but it also confirms that they have the latter truth and not the former as their aim. Thus experience reveals that philosophical works seem to preserve their inde structibility in the way works of art do, by means of an internal truth (veritas in re) which is entirely different from their claimed truth of judgment (veritas in repraesentando). But it reveals at the same time that in order to create these works, the philosopher does not aim at them in and for themselves, but always, like the scientist, at the discovery of a truth of judgment, of a theory conforming to the reality of things. The union of these two characters is what establishes the irreducibility of philosophy to either science or art neither of these characters can be stricken out to the benefit of the other without mutilating the fact. To uphold that all philosophy is created like a work of art because it can maintain itself like a work of art through the very value of an intrinsic truth, is to mutilate the experience which teaches us, on the contrary, that the two creations are utterly different. Consequently, to uphold this would render the solution to the transcendental problem impossible, a problem of legitimacy which can only be resolved when based on the unmutilated fact.”

We have here a very interesting picture of history of philosophy and also for philosophy of history. Gadamer we have seen sought to assimilate Truth to experience of art and he sees a philosophical text as a work of art embedded within its time but nevertheless suggesting something to us to understand which requires a fusion of horizons between the work of art and the historian. But Gueroult would point out that this is possible only if the work of art possesses an inner truth that is capable of being grasped or understood by the historian. This inner truth may differ in a work of art, in history of philosophy or political or social history. But it is this inner truth that allows a historian to access and understand the piece of art he is striving to comprehend. If our problem was confined to art then Gadamer’s understanding of Truth may have sufficed. Art is a mediator in suggesting to us the true meaning that is disclosed or uncovered in aesthetic consciousness where the meaning presents itself. But the case of history of philosophy presents a problem that shows we cannot extrapolate this case to every case of study of history and hence it is not a model for human sciences. The truth we are after in human sciences is not the same Truth that Gadamer finds in art. So either he is wrong in working out an ontology of art or else his idea of Truth is too restrictive and unsuitable for human sciences. For Gueroult art is an object of study in itself because of the inner truth it presents. In this way his understanding of aesthetic consciousness is different from Gadamer’s.

The demand that history of philosophy saddles on a philosopher and historian alike is to accommodate the structure of a philosophical system with its historical truth. The structure itself is a-temporal but history is a study embedded in time. Gueroult says this is only possible if there is an inner truth or structural truth within philosophy that is posited in virtue of a claim to scientific truth. This inner truth can be the object of study both for the philosopher and the historian (the two really cannot come apart in this case) because the inner truth is posited in virtue of a claim to scientific truth and the two are related; so the study of one necessitates the study of the other. A science needs to be a body of knowledge justifying its claim to Truth via an inner truth of the order of reasons so arranged that it can be assessed by standards of scientific Truth. We cannot have one without the other. Seen as an inner order of reasons a philosophical system is like a work of art capable of being studied for its own sake and as a past monument built with a pretension of serving as absolute truth. So the historian’s demand is satisfied. This way contra Gadamer we don’t need to reduce philosophical truth to truth of art and we don’t need to see contingent factors of its existence (social factors for instance) as essential to it. Contra Gadamer a work of art can be studied for its own sake and can have an inner truth. Its truth does not consist in its suggestiveness or mediation or implicit reference to another. Contra Logical Positivism philosophy is not simply a science; its claim to absolute truth is not factual but based on an inner truth of reasons which may survive the failure in its claim to absolute truth so that a philosopher still has something to learn from his past unlike the scientist. 

But how do we see the relation between one philosophical system and another? It is here that we need to depart from Gueroult. Historians of philosophy like Gilson take philosophical systems to be a system of abstract concepts that are discovered and worked out by individual philosophers. Victor Delbos believes that the force of a philosophical system depends on its flexibility in structure. Contra Gilson it is not an eternal and static structure of concepts. To quote Delbos:

“……if the internal force of a doctrine is measured by the degree of organization it implies, one could also say, conversely, that its historical influence is measured by the degree of disorganization it can sustain without becoming fundamentally denaturalized.” Consequently, “what we must aim a rediscovering and unearthing is the strong and flexible unity of a philosophy which, without modifying itself essentially, has managed to adapt to the most different conditions of existence.” (Tr. Mogens Laerke in his article Structural Analysis and Dianoematics)

Gueroult’s conception is closer to Gilson’s when he says, “Philosophy appears to itself as eternally valid in itself, a-temporally” but he departs in his understanding of philosophia perennis in so far contra Gilson there is no abstract structure: “There are no general structures, but only individualized structures, inseparable from the contents attached to them.” (Tr. Mogens Laerke in his article Structural Analysis and Dianoematics) The structure of a philosophical system is imparted to it by an individual like a work of sculpture owes its form to the sculptor. There is no one philosophia perennis but many. Hence Knox Peden in his Spinoza Contra Phenomenology characterizes Gueroult’s system as ahistorical and pluralistic. It is a study of radically disconnected systems of philosophy. This has striking consequences because every philosophical system is incommensurable with another. What happens to the common reality that every philosophical system stakes a claim to? Gueroult answers:

“The relation to the real is the condition of possibility of all philosophy. By this, however, it is by no means determined what reality it is about, nor the nature of that reality.”

And,

“The common reality has been posited as indeterminate and open to all the determinations that the different systems manage to attribute to it, each within its sphere.”

“The common reality appears as an internal law, purely formal, of philosophizing thought; a law that is indeterminate with regard to content; a law that grounds the necessity through which the different real syntheses of the interior and the exterior are possible for the philosophizing thought, syntheses each of which constitute a system or philosophical reality.”

“…….the concept of a completely undetermined common reality remains as the condition of possibility of the living philosophical experience in history”

(Tr. Mogens Laerke in his article Structural Analysis and Dianoematics)

Contra Gueroult if these radically incommensurate antagonistic systems were mutually exclusive then there couldn’t be a common reality and hence no conflict and what can then one hope to learn from another philosophy. If the common reality they aspire to is indeterminate then either every philosophical system posits the Truth or the very attempt to arrive at Truth is hopeless. And is Gueroult’s history of history of philosophy one way to understand history of philosophy or the only way to do so. If Gueroult claims the latter then he is contradicting himself. Hence we see in the end Gueroult stretches the a-temporality of philosophy to an extreme from where it precipitately falls from into the ditch from where he sought to rescue it. 

Fortunately there may be a way out. Gueroult’s problem revealed in the very formulation of his aporia for history of philosophy is that either philosophy can be temporal or philosophical but not both. We have seen that Delbos believed that there is a unity within a philosophical system that allows it to subsist despite change. This unity is not static and is not opposed to flexibility of the philosophical system. So the question is why a philosophical system cannot be both philosophical and historical – have we not saddled ourselves with two contradictory options that are really not contradictory at all even though mutually opposed to each other? This seems counter-intuitive because it seems to be the simultaneous assertion of temporality and a-temporality; clearly it is not possible for something to be both temporal and a-temporal. But we can understand the matter this way. There is only one philosophia perennis and not many contra Gueroult because there is one a-temporal Truth and one common reality that all philosophical systems aspire to. But an individualized structure of philosophy is a human construct representing the aspiration to capture this common reality and it is related to every other philosophical system dialectically i.e. in its attempt to find the right internal order of reason to make the claim for Truth. Every philosophical system seeks to get this internal order right in order to justify its claim to absolute truth. Hence philosophy progresses dialectically via ‘asking and giving reasons’ (to quote Robert Brandom). This approach does not condemn us to seeing a philosophical system as rigid or static instead of dynamic but rather it gives meaning to the system which may be dynamic. A thinker’s thoughts always try to achieve systematicity which is because every thought is in some way or other connected with another thought and a thinker may perhaps not always grasp these connections. Hence it is imperative to concentrate on the thought and understand a thinker in terms of his thoughts and not the other way round. Thought is dialectical; that it is best understood in terms of what it includes and what it excludes and it is always opposed to some other way of thinking and there is no way to understand the thought without understanding what it is opposed to. Hence contra Descartes philosophy is not a solo act; but it is essentially dialogical and dialectical which is also the reason we should be studying other philosophers; not to bring them to judgment as Bennett et al seek to do but to learn and practice and participate in philosophy itself. And this is the reason why philosophers in every century have found it necessary to study other philosophers for in the process they discovered their own philosophy.

One approach to philosophy is akin to Gueroult’s and of mystics and philosophers like Descartes. Elevate yourself to a higher sphere where there is no conflict but where there is the pure light of reason which itself will show you the way. This is the way of conquest - you rise above conflict and find your way to truth in a sphere of self-consciousness where the other is excluded and you are alone with truth. The second way is the way of the dialectician and philosophers like Aristotle where you embrace conflict instead of running away and you are self-conscious not because of exclusion but inclusion of the other. Your self-consciousness is determined by opposition to it and your way forward depends on a continuous synthesis of opposites. It does not require the exclusion of the whole for the parts or the parts for the whole. What matters here is not the end but the means; not the destination but the journey. You steadily employ your reason as far as your abilities allow you to and instead of looking for a knockout blow you look for steady but sure progress. Such a philosopher is not a conqueror but an explorer who will look at every single detail in light of the beauty of the whole because he is in no hurry to leave it to arrive at the end.

In the sphere of logic the point can be understood thus - instead of looking for demonstration - the kind you find in mathematics - you look for discussion and friction to move forward. It is reflection and serious consideration of opposing points of views which eventually through the friction it produces allows us to see the light. Philosophers today and even many in the past have been too impatient to arrive at the truth and make a conquest; so much so that those who did not find a demonstration of truths embraced scepticism or nihilism. They would have done well to accept conflict and uncertainty; nay even embrace it for they can never be eliminated. We have to learn to work our way despite them if not without them. Demonstrations condemn us to one principle and one method with which to arrive at the truth but dialectics open us to different perspectives. The world is multifaceted and rigidity is a sign of weakness while pliability is a sign of strength.

This does not imply that philosophy is devoid of significance for an individual. The point of philosophy is self-knowledge.

We go about living our lives unreflectively depending more on skills than knowledge. When we begin to reflect on practical everyday aspect of things it turns out that even though we are familiar with them; we do not really understand what we are doing. Through reflection we try to bring to attention what we are used to regarding as obvious so that we can gain a reflective understanding about its content. This theoretical understanding can then be integrated with practice to make it all the more effective. However the aim of theoretical rationality is truth; to understand why something is the way it is. In order to achieve that reason is the only tool we’ve got; it is only through rationalizing phenomena - trying to understand why something is the way it is and not through factual knowledge that we gain understanding.

Facts themselves yield only information not knowledge for knowledge requires us to connect the dots and understand facts within a theory where their correct place in the scheme of things can be found – to understand the whole rather than just the parts. Also it is imperative that to achieve such understanding the philosopher must rely on himself alone; he must take responsibility of his thinking process rather than defer to someone else’s views. The reasoning must be developed within the consciousness of the philosopher - he must be conscious of the reasons he has for a belief and be aware of his presuppositions as far as possible. The point of reasoning is not just to implement a method but to be reflectively aware of why he is employing a method and what he hopes to achieve by it. He must be aware of what he is doing and why. This reflective control can only be achieved through reasoning and self-knowledge - which is the primary aim philosophy.

But self-knowledge cannot be achieved in isolating the individual from the world but in relation to rest of the world. It should be noted here that we have departed from both Gueroult and Gadamer while preserving what is most valuable in both. This we have done by ridding ourselves of a false dichotomy between temporal and a-temporal Truth. Truth itself is a-temporal but the pursuit of truth is temporal and that does not preclude it from arriving at the absolute Truth. Absolute Truth is present to an individual as an ideal or as a value. A value to use Hartmann’s metaphor is like a guiding star that gives us direction. The philosophical system is a philosophia perennis where there is no distinction between inner truth and absolute truth because of its comprehensiveness while an individualized philosophical system aspires to philosophia perennis but lacks that level of comprehensiveness. In this case we can distinguish between the inner truth of a philosophical system and the absolute truth it aspires to and in light of the latter we may try to evaluate the former. Dialectics is concerned with the inner truth which need not be rigid and static and incommensurable with other philosophical aspirations. Rather the inner truth of any individualized system can contribute to human understanding as such and allow us to improve and reduce the gap between absolute truth and inner truth. Progress in philosophy should not be seen as diachronic progress but as synchronic progress in terms of depth of reflection contributing to the inner truth of a philosophical system which also necessarily implicates the progress in inner consciousness of the philosopher.

 

PHILOSOPHY OF SOCIAL SCIENCE

John Elster in his book Alchemies of the Mind says that the goal of study for social sciences is to identify causal mechanisms which he defines as: “frequently occurring and easily recognizable causal patterns that are triggered under unknown conditions or with indeterminate consequences.” A mechanism he says allows us to explain but not predict. Social Sciences have not and cannot discover law-like regularities but it can find causal mechanisms. Elster gives the examples of Alexis Tocqueville’s Democracy in America and Paul Veyne’s Bread and Circuses, which explore the interaction between beliefs, desires and norms of 19th Century America and its implications within America’s political institutions. Another example is the invisible hand theory developed by Adam Smith in his books The Wealth of Nations. It is not the case that depending on circumstances these mechanisms cannot come apart but nevertheless the study of these mechanism allows us to understand our institutions and the divergences can be instructive in their own way.

My only problem here is that this definition is not wrong but incomplete. Selection and discovery of the right mechanism requires as a background the understanding of a system as such or to take our clue from the preceding discussion of the inner truth of a system or a structure. Hence the object of study of a social science is the structure of society or the entire system as such. I would also plead that economics and social science should be seen identical wit political science (this is the way Ancient Greeks used to see it but in recent times economists like Ha-Joon Chang have argued that seeing economics as different from politics is a distortion and impedes our vision of the social system). It is not possible to study a structure in exclusion from its external environment. For instance floods, drought etc. influence decisions in society to migrate. It is the dynamic interaction between a social structure and its external environment which presents it with challenges to elicit response that is our concern. History is concerned with the study of social – political – economic systems (or of disciplines like philosophy, science or art) of the past and figure out the changes that occurred in these and their impact on the individual.

So society is a system which seeks to govern itself in light of certain values and principles (as per its understanding) or can be seen to fall short while retaining an inner truth or a structure or order to approximate certain values in its conduct much like a philosophical system outlined in the previous section. This is not to say that they share the same structure rather they have different structures and hence we need to adjust our methods to study them accordingly. Science has a more factual structure but contra Gadamer culture is not the sole concern of humanities; otherwise human beings would be cut from nature and understanding of nature is an important part of human culture. Philosophy has a structure that is irreducible to art or science. The structure of politics – economics – social science is the same but differ only in emphasis.

It is important to understand what a structure is and what the relation between an individual and the system is as such. Society is not just a collection of individuals it is also a system that binds people together. That is what distinguishes them from a crowd. A crowd has no basis of unification; no common goal, no mutual interest. But a system is created when people for a common purpose can be united together. We see that in everyday life. Rabindranath Tagore in his book, ‘Nationalism’ distinguishes between society and nation. Society he says is based on social adjustment and regulation of relationship between human beings understood as social beings. Nations he says are founded on greed, jealousy, suspicion and lust for power. Nationalism as an ideology is a subversive instrument that is used by governments to further their own agenda. Society is not divisive; ideologies are divisive.

The point of having a system or an order is that it should lead to the good of an individual. If we stress on individuality beyond a point then the system comes apart and that cannot be for the good of an individual. The question is how to solve the antinomy between the individual and the system. If the system is preferred over the individual then it benefits no one i.e. furthers no good and if the individual is given preference over the system then that would be to the detriment of the individual because without organization individuals cannot further their own interests. We need to strike the right balance between the two so that on the one hand an individual can maintain his individuality without being assimilated into the larger whole and on the other he can be a true unit or part of the whole and thereby contribute both to his own good and towards the greater whole.

Napoleon made a very interesting statement:

1. Society is impossible without inequality

2. Inequality intolerable without a code of morality

3. And a code of morality unacceptable without religion

1.1 If everyone were self-sufficient in every possible way there would be no society. This is the reason for the first statement. We are always in quest for equality; ironically without inequality there would be no society. Nature has not created us equal; this is something that is common to everyone so why not base the quest for equality on this. If equality is seen as a mathematical equation or in accounting terms where both sides should be balanced then such an equality is impossible. We should now be aware of this seeing the fate of communist regimes. The problem with a mathematical conception of equality is that it ignores what is truly good for an individual. For e.g. your neighbour has bought a car and out of jealousy you are driven to get an equally expensive car yourself despite knowing that you don’t need to make an unnecessary expenditure. But even if the person gets an expensive car there is no equality between him and his neighbour for the former’s interest has not truly been served. The purpose of a just society is to allow an individual to grow; to realize his potential - to get what he truly wants i.e. to give him an opportunity to live his life the best way he or she can. In this consists true equality.

1.2 But in order to achieve this end we need to regulate the conduct of an individual towards another so that despite whatever disparity exists between one individual and another in terms of what nature has provided one or the advantages his birth may have conferred on him; there is a basic and inviolable space or limit transgressing which one is liable to misconduct. If a small plant is not given adequate protection and care it shall not grow to be a tree. Leaving it to the mercy of everyone else does not make it equal to everyone for his needs and his interests are different from others. If this were not the case we should abandon small children to earn their living themselves so that they can be ‘equal’ to other earning members. But sensibly we do not do that because we know the kid needs adequate training and experience to be fit enough to cope with the world. Coming back these limits are rights and duties; both invariably go together. My right is what another owes to me and my duty what I owe to another. Laws are intended to protect these rights. And the rules that regulate the conduct of one individual towards another crystallize in a code of morality that a society chooses to abide with.

1.3 But if rights are my entitlement then on what basis do we decide who is entitled to what? Why is a code of morality not an expression of individual whims and fancies? What then is the basis of the mandate for rights and duties and laws in a society? Why should we follow them? What is it that makes them moral? Hence the need to base it on a Divine Mandate as conservatives have done. But this unacceptable for many reasons like every religion does not have the same thing to say and what God has said is subject to interpretation by few select men. Whence the objectivity of the mandate then? The basic problem is our sense of morality should be a judge when it comes to religion; rather than religion dictating what should be regarded as right or wrong - religion itself should be judged on the basis of our moral sense. Liberals go to the other extreme basing the mandate on human nature which is inconstant and often immoral. Hence social rules and regulations become a matter of practical expediency. But can we consider slavery to be moral on the basis of its practical utility? Hence the mandate should be sought in moral values themselves. Once the principle is determined and expressed in terms of rights and duties one needs to be concerned about the application of the principles to particular situations. Hence laws and constitutions are like strategy to determine the way certain moral values should be applied and protected from misconduct. But their force comes from social will to accept certain moral values and accept certain limitations to regulate their conduct in accordance with those values. This social will has to manifest itself in everyday life practices without which laws are just ink on paper. Hence the mandate is the social will coupled with moral values that a society chooses as its guiding star. This does not mean it is incumbent on us to blindly follow rules for to respond to challenges that a society meets it has to constantly scrutinize whether its rules and regulations are serving an end to follow the spirit of a value system or have become an end in itself. And one has to constantly think - what is the best way to apply a principle to situations of everyday life and there would always be more than one way to do so and there are no rules that tell us which rules are best. Also one needs to go beyond the liberal – conservative dichotomy.

The positions and arguments that the author have held in this paper are admittedly sketch and need filling out. The author has hoped to convey his general orientation to these problems and their motivations. For further improvement he can only plead time.

BIBLIOGRAPHY

ARISTOTLE (2001), BASIC WORKS OF ARISTOTLE ED. RICHARD MCKEON

DESCARTES, RENE (1984), PHILOSOPHICAL WRITINGS OF DESCARTES TR. JOHN CUTTINGHAM ETC.

ELSTER, JON (1999), ALCHEMIES OF THE MIND

GADAMER, HANS-GEORG, (1989), TRUTH AND METHOD 2ND REVISED EDITION

GUEROULT, MARTIAL (1969), THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY AS A PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEM (ARTICLE PUBLISHED IN THE MONIST)

GRONDIN, JEAN (1999), THE PHILOSOPHY OF GADAMER (TR. KATHYRN PLANT)

HEMPEL, CARL (1942), THE FUNCTION OF GENERAL LAWS IN HISTORY (JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY)

LAERKE, MOGENS (2019), STRUCTURAL ANALYSIS AND DIANOEMATICS: THE HISTORY OF HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY ACCORDING TO MARTIAL GUEROULT (DRAFT VERSION)

LEIBNIZ, GOTTFIED (1969), PHILOSOPHICAL PAPERS AND LETTERS TR. LEROY LOEMKER

PEDEN, KNOX (2014), SPINOZA CONTRA PHENOMENOLOGY

ROSEN, STANLEY (1993), THE QUESTION OF BEING

SALMON, WESLEY (1989), FOUR DECADES OF SCIENTIFIC EXPLANATION

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Criticism of Karma Theory

  Karma is a theory that believes that there is a moral providence in the world. The nature of this providence is to reward good and punish evil actions. But there are four big problems with it: Injustice is a patent fact in the world. On the other hand Karma theory would have us believe that contrary to our everyday life experiences there is complete justice in the world. People get what they deserve. Hence blame the one who suffers. Anyone who is enjoying his riches even though ill won is a good man. How many times do we see that something bad happens to someone who is good and something good happens to morally reprehensible people? The theory of karma is not a theory that arises from the need to explain our everyday life experiences. It is a dogma and forces us to interpret our experience in the light of this dogma. Since it cannot explain why there is injustice and misfortune in the world it posits the concept of rebirth. One proposition is sought to be validated through another un

Jiddu Krishnamurti - The Movement Of Thought

  There is conflict inner and outer when the world presents a challenge to an individual and demands a response. The mind in order to deal with an ever changing world imposes a certain pattern on it based on past experiences and which has a means – end structure. This gives direction to all human actions which are teleological i.e. they are always goal directed. How exactly does such a process arise? Three distinct processes can be discerned but these should not be seen in a chronological but in a functional sense: a)       Means – End Structure First there is sensation, pleasant, unpleasant or neutral. Memory records it and mind projects a future state where that same sensation can be either repeated or avoided. Thought arises parasitic on memory and allows the perpetuation or the continuity of the past. This is the beginning of psychological time – a past state seeking continuity in the future and conditioning response in the present. Thus JK says that the movement of thought is

SCHOOLS OF INDIAN THOUGHT – PART 1 – RAMANUJA’S VISHISTHADVAITA VEDANTA

  SCHOOLS OF INDIAN THOUGHT – PART 1 – RAMANUJA’S VISHISTHADVAITA VEDANTA APRITHAKSIDDHI : The central concept of VisishtAdvaita Philosophy is that Brahman alone is organically related to the soul (chit) and matter (achit) and is the ultimate reality. Chit and Achit are absolutely different and yet inseparable from Brahman. Though these two entities draw their very existence from Brahman. Brahman is independent of them just as the soul is independent from the body but remains the inner controller of both chit and achit. This relationship of inseparability is called Aprithaksiddhi. Empirically we find that a substance and an attribute though different yet are related to each other inseparably. Take for example a blue jar. The jar is different from the colour blue but both are referred to in the judgment, “This is a blue jar”. Perception reveals them to be identical but yet they cannot be identical, for jar is certainly different from the blue colour and not all jars are blue nor is