Leibniz’s conception of substance
differs in important ways from Descartes and Spinoza. A substance in Leibniz’s
philosophy is a monad and its characteristic mark is unity:
“It is worth
investigating in what way a being through aggregation, such as an army or even
a disorganized multitude of men, is one; and in what way its unity and reality differ
from the unity and reality of a man. . . . The chief point is this: an army accurately
considered is not the same thing even for a moment, for it has nothing real in
itself that does not result from the reality of the parts from which it is
aggregated; and since its entire nature consists in number, figure, appearance
and similar things, when these change it is not the same thing, but the human
soul has its own special reality so that it cannot come to an end by any change
in the parts of the body.” (Letter to Arnauld)
An aggregate
always presupposes a unity because an aggregate is nothing but a collection of
simple things (Monadology 2) and non-derivative unity can belong only to that
which is simple or without parts. These simple entities can be nothing else but
monads. If they are taken to be atoms in the way conceived by Epicurus
possessing extension then since anything that possesses extension is infinitely
divisible it cannot be said to possess the true unity out of which compound
entities can be composed. Neither can these atoms be like mathematical points
completely lacking in extension because if they themselves lack extension then
they cannot compose extension and since extension presupposes continuity of a
body it is evident that an extended body cannot be composed of mathematical
points. Besides we cannot account for the presence of force in the world either
on the atomic theory or in the Cartesian theory where matter is extension.
Force cannot be deduced from extension. We have to look for a metaphysical
cause for force within a substance or a monad.
The question of
the relation between a whole and its part is a difficult one. If the existence
of the whole is emphasized over the parts in the way Spinoza does then the
parts have to be taken to be an abstraction and hence unreal. While
countenancing the reality of parts over the whole would compromise the reality
of the whole for it would cease to be a unity and become an abstraction from
the parts. Hence we require a view where the relation between wholes and parts
must be such that neither compromises the independence of parts nor does it
destroy the unity of the whole. We will see how Leibniz sought to accomplish
this goal through his monads and whether he was successful in his endeavour or
not.
What is a
substance? And what is its essence and what are its attributes? In a Letter to
Foucher, Leibniz admitted that thought is not the essence of the soul:
“The author is
right in saying that thought is not the essence of the soul, for a thought is
an act, and since one thought succeeds another that which remains during this
change must necessarily rather be the essence of the soul, since it remains always
the same. The essence of substances consists in the primitive force of action,
or in the law of the sequence of changes, as the nature of the series consists
in the numbers.”
The nature of a substance is to
act; if it would cease to act it would cease to exist. To what end does it act?
It acts according to an inner law bestowed upon it by God and which lead to the
orderly production of a series of states of the monad. Each of these states of
a monad which are produced according to an inner law are representational
states and the production of these states occurs in harmony with the states or
the changes that occur in other monads. Thus no change within a monad occurs by
chance; they occur in accordance with a pre-established harmony between an
infinite numbers of monads. Every monad represents every other monad in the
world from its own distinctive point of view and this distinctive point of view
is what individuates a monad and explains the difference of one monad from
another. No two monads can share the same point of view.
The representative states of a
monad are of three types: a) perception b) appetition and c) apperception.
Perception is simply representation which is defined by Leibniz thus:
“One thing expresses another (in my sense)
when there is a constant and regular relation between what can be said of the
one and what can be said of the other. It is thus that a projection in
perspective expresses the original figure'” (Letter to Arnauld).
Perception is a state that
expresses or represents every other monad according to the law of
pre-established harmony without which there would be no order in the world of
monads and hence no constant and regular relation for monads are ‘windowless’ –
they do not interact with one another. Appetition is an ‘internal principle
which produces change or passage from one perception to another’ (Monadology
15). Consider an arrow moving in one direction. It wouldn’t change course till
something obstructs its passage and forces it to change course. Similarly a
monad will be stuck with one perceptual state only if there is no internal
force that does not obstruct it and allow passage to another perceptual state.
Leibniz distinguishes his theory of force from the scholastic theory and
Cartesian theory on grounds that it is neither motion nor a potentiality for
motion but something in between – a striving for something (this is similar to
conatus in Spinoza’s theory). Apperception is consciousness or thought. When a
perceptual state is accompanied by thought we become conscious of it and it
becomes possible to acquire knowledge. Self-Consciousness thus for Leibniz is
an achievement or a development in the state of a monad; contra Descartes it is
not simply present as a primitive state to us. In Monadology.30 Leibniz says:
“It is
by the knowledge of necessary truths and by their abstract expression that we
are raised to acts of reflexion which make us think of what is called "I,"
and observe that this or that is within us: and thus, in thinking of ourselves,
we think of being, of substance, of the simple and the compound, of the
immaterial and of God Himself, conceiving that what is limited in us is in Him
without limits. And these acts of reflexion furnish the chief objects of our reasoning.”
Distinguishing
between perception and apperception also helps Leibniz to account for the
existence of mind in deep sleep state. In New Essays Leibniz elaborates on his
theory of petites perceptions:
“The perceptions are
still there, but having lost the attractions of novelty, they are not strong
enough to claim our attention and memory, which are directed to more
interesting objects. For all attention requires memory; and often, when we are
not, so to speak, warned and directed to take notice of certain of our own
present perceptions, we let them pass without reflexion, and even without
observing them; but if someone immediately afterwards draws our attention to
them, and speaks to us, for instance, of some noise that has just been heard,
we recall it to ourselves and perceive that a moment ago we had some
consciousness of it. Thus there were perceptions of which we were not aware at
the time, apperception arising in this case only from our attention having been
drawn to them after some interval, however small.”
Even
though thought is not the essence of the soul; action is and even in deep sleep
state the mind is continually producing perceptual states even though we are
not conscious of these.
There is
an interpretive difficulty here – if apperception is taken to be consciousness
then perceptual states would be unconscious states of the soul. If perceptual
states are taken to have minimal level of consciousness then there is no
unconscious within Leibniz’s philosophy as Wundt believed. What then is the
status of petites perceptions? Leibniz’s views are not clear on this matter but
from his principle of continuity which says that no changes occur in a leap we
can infer that perceptual states of the soul must have some minimal amount of
consciousness to be eventually transformed through attention and memory into a
self-conscious state. An unconscious would in Leibniz’s view would then be a
confused or indistinct perception.
Coming
to substance and attributes in Discourse on Metaphysics Section 8, Leibniz
draws the distinction between substances and attributes:
“We must consider,
then, what it means to be truly attributed to a certain subject. Now it is certain
that every true predication has some basis in the nature of things, and when a proposition
is not an identity, that is to say, when the predicate is not expressly
contained in the subject, it must be included in it virtually. This is what the
philosophers call in-esse, when they say that the predicate is in the subject.
So the subject term must always include the predicate term in such a way that
anyone who understands perfectly the concept of the subject will also know that
the predicate pertains to it. This being premised, we can say it is the nature
of an individual substance or complete being to have a concept so complete that
it is sufficient to make us understand and deduce from it all the predicates of
the subject to which the concept is attributed. An accident, on the other hand,
is a being whose concept does not include everything that can be attributed to
the subject to which the concept is attributed.”
The notion of a subject involves all its predicates but not vica versa.
Next
we come to the degree of clarity and distinctness of representational states.
In his ‘What Is an Idea’, Leibniz defines an Idea thus:
“First
of all, by the term idea we understand something which is in our mind.”
This
distinguishes Ideas from traces of sense-impressions which are really in the
brain. Next:
“In my opinion,
namely, an idea consists, not in some act, but in the faculty of thinking, and
we are said to have an idea of a thing even if we do not think of it, if only, on
a given occasion, we can think of it.”
And to say that an idea is innate is to say:
“That the ideas of
things are in us means therefore nothing but that God, the creator alike of the
things and of the mind, has impressed a power of thinking upon the mind so that
it can by its own operations derive what corresponds perfectly to the nature of
things. Although, therefore, the idea of a circle is not similar to the circle,
truths can be derived from it which would be confirmed beyond doubt by
investigating a real circle.”
We will come back
to the theory of innate ideas later. For now we need to understand that no two
monads can share the same distinctive standpoint from which they represent the
world for otherwise they would be the same. This distinctive standpoint is understood
in terms of a quantity of perfection found in the monads and which is intrinsic
to a monad. Every monad exists within a continuum possessing a certain grade of
perfection from which it differs from every other monad and within the series
of monads the next one would possess a level of perfection a notch higher than
the previous one in the same series. This degree of perfection signifies the extent
of clear and distinct perception that the monad is capable of having. Every
monad since it represents every other is not thereby conscious of the entire
series of monads for slight imperfection clings to every monad except God.
Hence in some measure every monad would have a confused or obscure perception
otherwise it would be omniscient. The idea is well expressed by Robert Latta
(1898):
“Confusedness is
simply a low degree of distinctness: the more perfect any perception or
representation is, the more distinct is it, while the less perfect it is, the
more is it confused. Thus the differences among the Monads consist entirely in
the various degrees of perfection or distinctness with which they perceive or
represent the universe. But as each Monad actually represents the whole
universe, however confusedly or imperfectly, and as each is essentially a force
or living principle, proceeding, by its own spontaneous activity, from one perception
to another, the distinct and the confused are not essentially separate from one
another, but it is possible for the confused perception to unfold into
distinctness. Each Monad contains the whole more or less confusedly within itself,
and by its appetition may rise to a more perfect state. Each Monad contains as
it were enfolded within itself all that it is to be. It is 'big with the future.'
It is like an exceedingly condensed algebraical statement which can be
indefinitely expounded: somewhat like the symbol n in the problem of
determining the relation between the lengths of the diameter and circumference
of a circle, with this very important difference, that the Monad reads itself off.
An Omniscient Being could see the reality and history of the whole universe
within the lowest Monad.”
Here certain
further terminological clarifications are required. I shall follow here
Leibniz’s Meditations on Knowledge, Truth and Ideas:
Knowledge can be
divided into clear and obscure:
Obscure Knowledge:
Does not suffice for the recognition of the thing represented.
Clear Knowledge:
Suffices for the recognition of the thing represented
Clear Knowledge
can be confused or distinct:
Confused: Ability
to distinguish something on the basis of sense-perception but with no idea of
its defining characteristic. The perception of colour is for instance confused
because even though it is taken to be a simple sensible element in sense-perception
it is still something that is composed of parts which though represented within
a monad is represented distinctly. Whenever we have some perception where the
parts of the thing perceived from indiscriminately grouped together or in other
words we are not aware of the parts that compose it but which can be revealed
through analysis; then we have a confused perception.
Distinct
Knowledge: When we know the real definition of something. We shall elaborate on
this later.
Distinct Knowledge
can be adequate or inadequate and symbolic or intuitive:
Adequate: Defining
marks are known distinctly
Inadequate:
Defining marks are known confusedly
Symbolic: Concepts
with parts obscurely understood
Intuitive:
Concepts whose parts are understood simultaneously with the whole. Primitive
concepts are understood by themselves for they are simple and hence can be
known only through intuition.
Only God’s
knowledge can be completely adequate. Since some imperfection always accrues to
the monads their knowledge will always in some part be obscure and confused.
We now come
to the basis on which Leibniz distinguishes between truths of facts and truths
of reason. In his First Truths Leibniz says that a simple primitive concept is
that of identity or what comes down to the same thing the law of non-contradiction.
A Truth of Reason either asserts an identity or is reducible through analysis
to an identity. Such a proof will be a-priori or independent of experience.
From this Leibniz infers his predicate in subject principle which says that
truth is nothing but a certain connection between subject and the predicate.
This connection is identity. Next Leibniz deduces his Principle of Sufficient
Reason which says that ‘nothing is found without a reason’ and ‘there is no
effect without a cause’. For every predicate we have to find its ground within
the subject to which it belongs otherwise that would imply that all Truths are
not identities or are not reducible to identities. Note that the notion of a
reason is broader that the notion of a cause because Leibniz says that we can
demand a reason for the existence of eternal things too. But both are
understood in terms of inherence of a predicate within a subject.
Next Leibniz
deduces his Principle of Identity of Indiscernibles which says that ‘there
cannot be two individual things which differ only numerically’; otherwise there
would be something in nature for which there is no reason i.e. why should there
be two things in nature that differ only numerically. It should be possible to
give some reason of their difference from one another and this reason can be
found only within their nature. Since every predicate belongs to its subject
necessarily (identity being a necessary relation) no two subjects can share the
same predicates and hence there cannot be ‘no purely extrinsic denominations
which have no basis at all within the denominated thing itself’. The Law of
Continuity is a corollary of this principle.
This implies that
a ‘complete or a perfect concept of an individual substance involves all its
predicates, past, present and future’. To this Arnauld objected that all that
would happen to Adam for instance would follow from a fatal necessity
destroying the chance of freedom. Leibniz’s reply in effect is that an essence
is the object of God’s Understanding and existence is the effect of God’s Will
or God’s decrees. God’s decision regarding which predicates would be found
within the concept of Adam depends on taking into consideration all other
possible individuals along with Adam. There is only a hypothetical necessity
involved here because God has to consider the best of all possible worlds to
actualize. And Adam would actualize the contents in the concept of Adam only if
God decides to actualize it within the scheme of things. It is important to
note that given the Principle of Identity of Indiscernibles it follows that
there can be no extrinsic denominations; all properties of a substance are
intrinsic to it and individuate it. Hence in modern terminology there cannot be
any possible world which would have an Adam but where he is not the first man.
All properties of Adam necessarily follow from the nature of Adam and are
likewise contained within the concept of Adam but no one save God can deduce
all predicates contained in the concept of the subject.
But here Arnauld
posed a dilemma for Leibniz. Either the notion of Adam is prior to the Divine
Will in which case the predicates which follow from the notion of Adam would be
intrinsic and necessary because they would be within Divine Understanding and
Leibniz admits that essences are objects of Divine Understanding prior to any
consideration of the Will. Or else they are posterior to Divine Will or in
other words created by the Divine Will in which case the connexion between the
predicates and the subject will neither be intrinsic nor necessary. To this
Leibniz replies that the connexion here is intrinsic without being necessary.
It is not necessary because what predicates Adam would have in the course of
its existence is decided by the Divine Will; those predicates are not so much
the consequence of the essence of Adam but of the essence of Adam along with a
possible decree of God. This presupposes the prior consideration of Adam’s
compatibility with the other notions and these possible predicates that he may
have is known a-priori under the condition of the possible decrees Adam may
actualize when he would exist. Hence the possibility that follows from the
essence and the possibility that follows from the concept of Adam are
different. The concept of Adam is compossible because the existence of Adam
does not follow from the essence of Adam and requires the institution of Divine
Will apart from Divine Understanding. The possibility of an essence is a
consequence of the law of non-contradiction while the possibility of the
concept of Adam follows from taking into consideration its compatibility with
other concepts which would be combined together within a single world.
Now we can
distinguish between truths of facts and truths of reason. Truths of reason
knowable a-priori require only true identities. All truths of reason are either
identities or reducible to identities. But truths of facts are contingent and
knowable via experience. They cannot be deduced straightforwardly from the
concept of a subject contra Descartes and Spinoza. Nevertheless they are
intrinsic to the subject or have their reason or ground for their existence
within the subject. The reconciliation of these apparently contradictory
notions requires us to reconceive the notion of identity. In the case of truths
of facts identities are not self-evident and do not simply require attending to
their presence within the subject but on the other hand require us to take into
consideration the compatibility of the predicate with the notion of every other
subject. Thus identity of predicates in case of Truths of facts requires
reference not only to its own subject but also to every other subject. These
identities are governed not simply by the principle of non-contradiction but by
the principle of pre-established harmony. Since every monad expresses another
and since it is the essence of every monad to express every other from its own
distinctive point of view; the identity of every monad contains an explicit or
implicit reference to every other. This requires change within traditional
logic which is a logic of being not of becoming. Martial Gueroult (1946) has
expressed this well:
“It does not
suffice for Leibniz to perceive in a general way that a certain mode is linked
to the substance and necessarily posited by it; he also needs to conceive why a
certain mode must occur at a certain determined moment in time. For a state
receives the full determination of its content only through its complete
connexion with all the other parts of the whole, therefore through the place
which is its own in space and in time. Thus the fundamental requirement of
rationalism, to reduce individual reality to a system of conceived relations,
can no longer be realized simply by conceiving how the particular predicates
are, in a general way, the con-sequences of the subject to which they belong.
That was what rationalism had been content with heretofore, when it tried to
establish the fundamental logical connection of things, and that is why it took
geometry for its model: just as it is included within the concept of the
triangle that the sum of its angles equals two right angles, so the foundation
of reality which embraces everything, engenders necessarily all the particular
determinations.”
And,
“The logic of the
school considered concepts as immobile entities given once and for all: the
qualifications which belong to a concept are its own in abstracto, in itself
and by itself. There is no question of a development in which they would
participate, nor of their changing and progressive production. Thus, what
follows from the nature of a thing belongs to it in an unchangeable fashion and
for all times. Leibniz on the contrary has taken hold of the problem of change
and has conceived it as a logical problem, and the concept of subject assumes
then a new meaning. It can no longer be, as it had been for formal logic, the
passive and inert support of multiple determinations, but it is conceived as
the active principle which positively creates them. It is only thus that the
logical subject is transformed into a metaphysical substance, that it is
thought of as the source and original foundation of the determinations which
are to proceed from it in the future according to a pre-established law. Thus
the idea of vital development renews the logical concept. On the other hand,
logic becomes more profound so as to account for this vital development and
submit it to a rational norm. The notion of vital development is united with
the adage: praedicatus inest in subject; differential calculus, by providing
the concept of the law of the series, which accounts for all details through
time, makes the rational coextensive with the becoming.”
The relation between whole
and parts thus should be understand as between the sign and the signified. The
part or the monad expresses the whole howsoever imperfectly and the whole is
expressed within each and every part. Cause-Effect relation is also understood
in terms of expression. One monad expresses another but when one expression is
confused in relation to the other then the former confused perception is seen
as the effect and the more distinct perception as the cause. Hence we think
that a certain external object is the cause of the sense-experience we have. We
take the external object to be active and the sense-experience to be passive.
The relation between cause and effect is the relation between different monads
and their expression of each other. Hence the relation of cause-effect lacks
analytic necessity but has synthetic necessity (to introduce Kantian terms)
which is understood in terms of the pre-established harmony or the
compatibility of everything with everything else instituted by God in each and
every monad. The substance or the monad however contra Descartes is still a
source of force or action even though the direction comes from an inner law
created by God. Hence such a substance does not require God to constantly
re-create it but can be a secondary source of action. Leibniz also goes past
Spinoza’s fatal necessity since God’s Will requires God’s Understanding to
choose the best of all possible world. The order of synthetic truths is not a
necessary consequence of the nature of God but the necessity involved here is a
moral necessity rather than a metaphysical necessity.
Finally we come to the topic
of innate ideas. In Leibniz’s system the Idea of God and Extension do not
reflect simple essence. Descartes has been too hasty to come to the conclusion
that an Idea is simple appealing merely to clear and distinct Ideas. An atheist
however would protest that he has no clear Idea of God to which Descartes’s
response would beg the question unless he shows how the atheist can have
similar experiences. Hence the clear and distinct criteria of truth lacks bite
and is empty. Human thought is symbolic and more often than not we take an Idea
to be simple which however is composed of parts which only further analysis can
reveal. We can thus understand Leibniz’s criticism of Descartes’s ontological
argument. To deduce the existence of God from the Idea of God requires first to
prove that the Idea of God is possible and this Descartes has simply assumed
because he takes it for granted that we can talk and think about God and thus
we have the Idea of God. But it is something that requires demonstration. The
Idea of God is shown to be possible by Leibniz by defining God as the subject
of all perfections and then providing a proof that all perfections may be
present within a subject without contradiction. The demonstration presupposes
that the Idea of God is itself composed on prior notions of perfections which
Leibniz understands to be positive, simple and indefinable. All these
perfections must have a reason grounded within their subject and this subject
is what we call God (Two Notations for Discussion with Spinoza, On Universal
Synthesis and Analysis or the Art of Discovery and Judgement and Meditations on
Knowledge, Truth and Ideas). We have a real as opposed to nominal definition of
something when we can demonstrate its possibility or show those properties that
tell us that something is possible.
The concept of extension also is
not simple as Leibniz argues:
“For an extended being implies the idea of a
continuous whole in which there is a plurality of things existing
simultaneously. To speak of this more fully, here is required in extension, the
notion of which is relative, a something which is extended or continued as
whiteness is in milk, and that very thing in a body which constitutes its
essence; the repetition of this, whatever it may be, is extension.”
Simple Truths are truths of
identities for Leibniz. Against Descartes he points out that in addition we
have truths of facts which require real grounds not just ideal grounds within
understanding. Since these truths are governed according to a pre-established
harmony they presuppose God as their source. Against Locke Leibniz points out
that there are Truths of Reason that cannot be known through
sensible-experience.
In Leibniz’s case it is enough to
define innate ideas in terms of objects of understanding. We have seen for
Leibniz to have an innate idea is to have a faculty or a disposition to
recognize certain Truths. But unlike in the case of Descartes we do not need to
demarcate these Truths in terms of their cause being God. It is sufficient to
point out that they are in understanding alone. The reason is first that
essence in Leibniz are eternal and are objects of God’s understanding and are
not created by God. Second, Descartes does not distinguish between truths of
facts and truths of reason. The former too have their source in human
understanding hence we found it difficult to exclude sense-experiences merely
by appealing to the nature of the thinking substance. But since Leibniz draws
this distinction it is enough to point out that these truths are found within
understanding alone. Third, Leibniz always begins with the perfect concept
which is the object of God’s Understanding (Letter to Arnauld). For Leibniz the
difference between human and divine understanding should be understood to be a
difference in quantity not in quality. Hence he finds no problem to begin with
a perfect concept even though human beings do not have a perfect concept. But
to ensure simplicity of primitive concepts in Leibniz we do not need to add any
clause about Divine Understanding.
We can also see how Leibniz steers the rationalist program from Gassendi’s and Malebranche’s arguments. Leibniz is in agreement with Gassendi and Malebranche that the Transparency Principle (Descartes: “….. Nothing can be in me of which I am entirely unaware.”) cannot be held and that thought is not the essence of the Substance. The soul can have petite perceptions of which it is not conscious. Self-consciousness is achieved through knowledge of principles or reason and it does not consist in beholding the vision of the self but necessarily involves reference to a world outside. The inward consciousness is achieved through the external consciousness – the two being intimately linked together.
But the objections raised against
Cartesian theory of substance cannot be raised against Leibniz. First, because
simple truths are for him either identities or reducible to identities they
have a claim to being self-evidently true and knowable a-priori. Second,
strictly there is a distinction between an essence and a substance. While the
former is absolutely simple, the latter is only relatively simple. The reason
is that existence cannot be deduced from essence and the concept of Adam for
instance is both the object of Divine Understanding and subject to possible
decrees of God which is the cause of existence and is added to an essence to
transform it into a substance. The distinction between substance and its modes
is not drawn by Leibniz on basis of possibility of one existing without the
other but on basis of conception of the substance being much more inclusive
than that of an attribute. Hence there is a strong intimate tie between a
substance and its modes – the latter is only an expression of the substance in
accordance with an inner law of sequence of changes and the substance cannot
exist without having some qualities or other. It necessarily is active. Third,
Leibniz draws the distinction between truths of reason and truths of facts.
While the condition of tracing every property of a substance back to its ground
in the substance is something Leibniz has in common with Descartes still he
does not believe that even though the connection between a subject and
predicate is of identity – we still cannot be aware of this identity in every
case. This is to say that in case of truths of facts we cannot deduce the
property from the substance or simply from the definition of the thing like in
the case of deduction of the Pythagorean property from the definition of the
triangle. Certain predicates are found within the subject due to its relation
to every other monad and its expression of every other monad instituted within
every monad by God’s Will in accordance with a pre-established harmony. Only
God can read the reason of every predicate that can be found within a subject. While
a perfect concept contains all predicates an entity can have in course of its
existence only God is capable of deducing the reason for all such predicates
from the concept of the substance. Human Beings lack that capacity. The
deduction of the predicate from the concept of the subject is a regulative
ideal for science but not one that is achievable. Since monads are infinite in
number the attempt to trace every predicate back to the subject would require
an infinite analysis for the process would implicate every other monad that is
represented within a single monad. Hence the monads themselves cannot be the
reason for the entire series of monads; only something outside the series of
monads can provide the reason for its existence. This reason is God. Fourth,
the practical inability to trace the source of truths of facts to monads
themselves does not compromise the rationalist program because it is a
regulative ideal. And unlike Descartes Leibniz believes that the primary
purpose of philosophy is not analysis but synthesis. Analysis traces back a
predicate to its ground in the subject. There is a reason that a predicate is
found in a subject and not in another. But as we have seen this is practically
impossible in the case of truths of facts for a sufficient reason for their
existence in the subject would require an implicit reference to other monads
which are infinite. Even Spinoza’s infinite substance cannot do justice to the
concrete reality which becomes unreal or an abstraction because of the emphasis
on the greater reality of the whole over the parts. Synthesis on the other hand
begins with the principles and attempts to understand the reason for the
existence of things in accordance with those principles. Consistent with his
philosophy there are two sets of principles required for this purpose.
Principles of understanding which are a-priori – the ideal ground for the
existence of the world and Principle of Sufficient Reason – the sufficient
reason for the existence of the series of monads we have seen is God and the
order of experiential truth depending on a pre-established harmony depends on
God’s benevolence and Wisdom for these truths are a matter of choice and not
metaphysical necessity but moral necessity. Hence in Leibniz’s philosophy we
come across a duality between ideal grounds and real grounds. Kant noted this
point and also the relation with his own philosophy. In his reply to Eberhard
he elaborates on Leibniz’s Pre-Established Harmony:
“Hence the connexion between understanding and
sense in the same subject can be understood according to certain a priori laws,
as well as the necessary and natural dependence of sense upon external things,
without sacrificing external things to idealism. For this harmony between
understanding and sense, in so far as it renders possible a priori the knowledge
of universal laws of nature, criticism has given as a reason that without this
harmony no experience is possible But we can give no reason why we have just such
a kind of sense and an understanding of such a nature that through their
combination experience is possible; and further we can find no reason why they,
as completely heterogeneous sources of knowledge, always so completely harmonize
in rendering possible experiential knowledge in general and more especially (as
the Critique of Judgment shows) in rendering possible an experience of nature,
under its manifold special and merely empirical laws, regarding which the
understanding teaches us nothing a priori. Neither we nor anyone else can
explain how this harmony is as complete as if nature had been arranged
expressly to suit our power of comprehension. Leibniz called the principle of
this union (especially with reference to the knowledge of bodies and in
particular of our own body as a middle term in this relation) a pre-established
harmony. Manifestly he did not in this way give an explanation of the union,
nor did he profess to explain it. He merely pointed out that we must regard the
order established by the supreme cause of ourselves as well as of all things
outside of us as involving a certain conformity to end.”
The division between sense and
intellect is not as radical in Leibniz as in Kant. For Leibniz sense perception
is a confused perception capable of becoming more distinct by the operation of
the intellect. But knowledge that may be acquired through experience cannot be
acquired through reason and vica-versa. The ground for the truth of facts
knowable through the senses and the ground for the truths of reason are
different. One can be traced to Divine Understanding and are necessarily true
both for us and for God and another to Divine Will depend on God’s choices and
hence are only contingently true. The predicates involved in both have a reason
or ground in the subject though in cases of contingent truths we are not
capable of knowing these reasons absolutely. They can ultimately be only
referred back to God. We can notice here a tension in Leibniz’s philosophy –
while he requires a difference in ideal and real grounds yet he also seeks
their greater unity which eludes him. We will have an opportunity to see that
Leibniz juxtaposes the Principle of Non-Contradiction with the Principle of
Sufficient Reason without being able to reconcile both.
However we can see now the inner
dialectic of the rationalist program quite clearly. It began with the demand to
trace everything that exists back to its essence in such a way that it could be
deduced from the essence itself. This required an inner contemplation of Ideas
and the ability to see clearly and distinctly the presence of a property in its
essence. A demonstration is nothing but a series of simple intuitions which
grasps the determination of a property of a determinable essence. The Principle
of Non-Contradiction is paramount here. We have an Idea if no contradiction in
involved within it and all truths can simply be deduced from this Idea. However
this elegant picture receives a setback with Gassendi and Malebranche pointing
out that the deductive ambitions are not achievable. For all its emphasis on
intelligibility there is an obscurity with the rationalist theory. The
obscurity in the notion of substance and the relation between substance and its
attributes has epistemological repercussions. The ability to trace every truth
back to its principles requires greater grasp of the principles themselves. But
this is absent from the Cartesian Paradigm for it requires grasping the essence
of a thinking substance that is capable through an inner awareness to grasp all
truths or principles found within it or are innate to it. But this capacity for
self-illumination to uncover the principles can never be proved for we are
unaware of the nature of this substance. And this piece of ignorance is because
the notion of substance itself is obscure. The fate of the Cartesian Program is
sealed with Leibniz drawing the distinction between truths of facts and truths
of reason and demonstrating that the simple essences Descartes believes he is
aware of are not really simple and that he took the analysis to be too simple a
task to accomplish which it is not. However he also rescues the rationalist
program by taking deduction of all predicates from the concept of a substance
as a regulative ideal and emphasizing synthesis to a greater extent than
analysis for we can be aware of reasons only through application of principles
to matters of fact. Even though Spinoza can be seen as emphasizing synthesis
over analysis Leibniz has a broader spectrum of principles for ideal truths and
real truths and unlike Spinoza he does justice to the reality of the parts as
well as of the whole and does not seek to reduce one to the other. But the
question is how successful is Leibniz in establishing a harmony between sense
and the intellect?
Comments
Post a Comment