The purpose of this paper
is to compare and contrast the arguments given by Vasubandhu in Vimsatika and
Dignaga in his Alambana-Pariksha on the one hand and George Berkeley in favour
of idealism on the other.
BERKELEY’S ESSE IS
PERCIPI ARGUMENT
Berkeley's argument for esse is
percipi idealism is
(1) ideas can exist only in being perceived
(2) sensible objects (stones, trees, mountains,etc.)
are ideas
(3) therefore, sensible objects can exist only
in being perceive
The rationale for premise (1) can be explained
through contrasting it with the views of Locke’s theory of Ideas which is
opposed by Berkeley:
“I must here in the Entrance beg pardon of my
Reader, for the frequent use of the Word Idea, which he will find in the
following Treatise. It being that Term, which, I think, serves best to stand
for whatsoever is the Object of the Understanding when a Man thinks . . . or
whatsoever it is, which the Mind can be employ’d about in thinking. (ECHU
I/i/§8)”
“Whatsoever the Mind perceives in itself, or
is the immediate object of Perception, Thought, or Understanding, that I call
Idea. (II/viii/§8)”
So Idea is being defined in terms of whatever
is present to consciousness when we are perceiving, thinking, imagining
something. This does not make the definition circular because Idea is being
used as an all-inclusive term for anything that we are thinking at that
particular moment. So the object of thought does not have any existence
independently of thought; there is no appearance – reality distinction
pertaining to the Idea – it’s being consists in being thought. There is nothing
wrong with defining Ideas in terms of presence to consciousness because this is
an irreducible notion.
But for Locke the sensed object can be
abstracted from sensation and can be posited to be an external cause of
sensation through inference whose cognitive ground is the sensation itself
(only in cases of primary qualities). This abstractionist move is blocked by
Berkeley through his ontological principle:
“Whether
others have this wonderful faculty of abstracting their ideas, they best can
tell: for myself I find indeed I have a faculty of imagining, or representing
to myself the ideas of those particular things I have perceived and of
variously compounding and dividing them. I can imagine a man with two heads or
the upper parts of a man joined to the body of a horse. I can consider the
hand, the eye, the nose, each by itself abstracted or separated from the rest
of the body. But then whatever hand or eye I imagine, it must have some
particular shape and colour. Likewise the idea of man that I frame to myself,
must be either of a white, or a black, or a tawny, a straight, or a crooked, a
tall, or a low, or a middle-sized man. . . . To be plain, I own myself able to
abstract in one sense, as when I consider some particular parts or qualities
separated from others, with which though they are united in some object, yet,
it is possible they may really exist without them. But I deny that I can
abstract one from another, or conceive separately, those qualities which it is
impossible should exist so separated. (PHK intr. §10)”
The principle states that the distinction
between X and Y is an ontological distinction only if X can be perceived to
exist independently of Y and vica-versa; otherwise the difference between the
two is a mere semantic distinction. Applying this to the above case the sensed
object does not exist independently of the sensation. We can abstract it from
the sensation as much as we like but what we cannot do is ascribe this
abstraction any ontological distinction. Since the sensed object has no
independent existence from the sensation (for e.g. pain is nothing apart from
painful sensations) Berkeley’s first premise in justified. The Idea and the
Ideatum are defined in terms of presence to consciousness and as incapable of
existing independently of one another. In his Commonplace Books he touches on
the importance of this innovation:
“Twas the opinion that Ideas could exist
unperceiv’d or before perception that made Men think perception was somewhat
different from the Idea perceiv’d, that it was an Idea of Reflexion whereas the
thing perceiv’d was an idea of Sensation. I say twas this made ’em think the
understanding took it in receiv’d it from without which could never be did not
they think it existed without. (C 656)”
And,
“I Defy any man to Imagine or conceive
perception without an Idea or an Idea without perception . . . Consciousness, perception,
existence of Ideas, seem to be all one” (C 572 and 578)
Thus the distinction between consciousness of
the sensation and the existence of the sensation is simply a semantic
distinction with no ontological consequences. This repudiation of the
act-object model of consciousness forms the first step in Berkeley’s proof of
idealism.
Coming to premise (2) Berkeley gives the
following justification for it in his Dialogues between Hylas and Philonaus:
“Ask the gardener, why he thinks yonder cherry
tree exists in the garden, and he shall tell you, because he sees and feels it;
in a word, because he perceives it by his senses. Ask him why he thinks an
orange tree not to be there, and he shall tell you, because he does not
perceive it. What he perceives by sense, that he terms a real being, and saith
it is, or exists; but that which is not perceivable, the same, he saith, has no
being. (3D234)”
And in PHK 4:
“If we thoroughly examine this tenet, it will,
perhaps, be found at bottom to depend on the doctrine of abstract ideas. For
can there be a nicer strain of abstraction than to distinguish the existence of
sensible objects from their being perceived, so as to conceive them existing
unperceived? Light and colours, heat and cold, extension and figures, in a word
the things we see and feel, what are they but so many sensations, notions,
ideas or impressions on the sense; and is it possible to separate, even in
thought, any of these from perception? For my part I might as easily divide a
thing from itself. I may indeed divide in my thoughts or conceive apart from
each other those things which, perhaps, I never perceived by sense so divided.
Thus I imagine the trunk of a human body without the limbs, or conceive the
smell of a rose without thinking on the rose itself. So far I will not deny I
can abstract, if that may properly be called abstraction, which extends only to
the conceiving separately such objects, as it is possible may really exist or
be actually perceived asunder. But my conceiving or imagining power does not
extend beyond the possibility of real existence or perception. Hence as it is
impossible for me to see or feel anything without an actual sensation of that
thing, so is it impossible for me to conceive in my thoughts any sensible thing
or object distinct from the sensation or perception of it.”
Berkeley consistently insists that he is not
changing anything but is with the common man in his proof for idealism because
he is merely making plain the meaning of the word ‘existence’. Philosophers
preceding Berkeley had made a division in the sense of existence in order to
make it more precise. The criteria for existence was causal efficacy and the
only properties or qualities that survived this criteria were primary qualities
like shape, size, mass, power etc. We cannot think of an object devoid of these
qualities but an object can exist without colour and hence this quality is not
on a par with others more essential to an object. Also primary qualities are
essential ingredients in the endeavour to explain the causal efficacy of an
object. Hence the sense in which the former exists is different from the sense
in which the latter exists. Also the former qualities are stable and constant
whereas colour is an inconstant quality; an object seems to be of a different
colour in broad daylight compared to when it is in shade or when some
reflection is falling on it and in complete darkness the colour is not
perceived at all. Hence there is a double sense of existence – one that can be
applied to primary qualities which is the sense in which something external to
the mind is said to exist and secondary qualities which have a mind-dependent
existence and are hence observer relative. Berkeley repudiates this picture to
form a single sense of existence which is more in keeping with the practices of
the vulgar.
The meaning of existence is to be determined
in terms of what meaning it has for us. The meaning it has for us is revealed
through actual sensation which is understood not only in terms of presence to
consciousness but as being inseparable from its consciousness. While in the
rationalist tradition meaning or definition of something depended on whether we
can conceive it without contradiction – which principle itself is derived from
the Principle of Non-Contradiction and is made manifest through principle like
Nothingness has no properties therefore if there is something then it possesses
some property or other. But Berkeley’s empiricism begins not with rational
principles but with asking what Ideas we have and all Ideas are intimately tied
to sensations. So if we have to clarify the meaning of existence then we will
have to look at the sensation or impression through which we acquire the notion
of existence. This project of tracing the origin of ideas back to their source
in sense-impressions are begun by Locke but it was made concrete through
Berkeley and completed later by Hume. Why Berkeley’s case for tracing the
source of the concept of existence to the actual sensation is stronger than
Locke’s can be understood from the fact that Locke’s critique of innatism is
vulnerable to Rationalist counter-arguments that even if sensation is required
to acquire the notion of existence that does not imply that the meaning or
definition of existence itself depends on this source. This practically was the
retort Locke got from Leibniz’s New Essays Concerning Human Understanding.
But Berkeley is not similarly vulnerable. The
reason is that firstly Berkeley has tightened up his case through his use of
the separability principle which allows him to define the existence of the
sensed object to sensation itself. Thus sensation is not a representation of
something external but is a reality in itself. It is both the sensation and
what is sensed. The inference to external sensed object is blocked on this way
to understand sensation. Secondly it is important to understand that if Berkeley
can show that the psychological means through which a concept is acquired
contributes to the content of that concept then rationalism is undermined. Thus
sensation does not simply reveal the meaning of existence but determines or
constitutes that meaning. Hence the meaning of trees, grass etc. that the
gardener learnt has as its necessary component the sensation of trees, grass
etc. and thereby what he means that trees etc. can exist unperceived is that
currently he has not sensation of trees and grass. As a consequence just as
pleasure and pain cannot be predicated of external objects regarded as the
cause of pleasure and paid similarly the application conditions of a concept is
similarly limited to the consciousness which is the defining feature of that concept
and thereby the concept of existence is restricted to the purview of actual
sensations and cannot be applied to external non-sensory objects for that would
be as Berkeley says in PHK 4 ‘a manifest contradiction’. This interpretation is
further supported by a passage that has troubled commentators but which
otherwise is amenable to be understood through this interpretation:
“But say you, surely there is nothing easier
than to imagine trees, for instance, in a park, or books existing in a closet,
and no body by to perceive them. I answer, you may so, there is no difficulty
in it: but what is all this, I beseech you, more than framing in your mind
certain ideas which you call books and trees, and at the same time omitting to
frame the idea of any one that may perceive them? But do not you yourself
perceive or think of them all the while? This therefore is nothing to the
purpose: it only shows you have the power of imagining or forming ideas in your
mind; but it doth not show that you can conceive it possible, the objects of
your thought may exist without the mind: to make out this, it is necessary that
you conceive them existing unconceived or unthought of, which is a manifest
repugnancy. When we do our utmost to conceive the existence of external bodies,
we are all the while only contemplating our own ideas. But the mind taking no
notice of itself, is deluded to think it can and doth conceive bodies existing
unthought of or without the mind; though at the same time they are apprehended
by or exist in itself. (PHK I §23)”.
We can see the process through which we have
reached this point. First Locke defines idea as whatever is the object of
thought or consciousness. Them he considers the status of the existent object
or the sensed object in the sensation or the Idea. Since Locke does not ascribe
to separability principle he takes the existence of the object of consciousness
to be inseparable from consciousness (appearance = reality principle) on
grounds of his the nature of mind being a substance which cannot apprehend anything
apart from its modes. But he allows through a process of abstraction the
extraction of the sensed object (in case of primary qualities only) from the
sensation and through inference posit its existence as an external reality.
Then Berkeley comes into picture and through his separability principle he
blocks this abstractive move confirming the definitional identity of the sensed
object and the sensation thereby espousing a psychologism which though implicit
in Locke was not endorsed by him or even intended by him. This radically
changes the nature of the debate between rationalism and empiricism; something
that Hume realized, as he says in his Treatise 1/1/1:
“’tis remarkable, that the present question
concerning the precedency of our impressions or ideas, is the same with what
has made so much noise in other times, when it has been disputed whether there
be any innate ideas, or whether all ideas be derived from sensation and
reflexion. We may observe, that in order to prove the ideas of extension and
colour not to be innate, philosophers do nothing but show, that they are
conveyed by our senses. To prove the ideas of passion and desire not to be
innate, they observe that we have a preceding experience of these emotions in
ourselves. Now if we carefully examine these arguments, we shall find that they
prove nothing but that ideas are preceded by other more lively perceptions,
from which they are derived, and which they represent.”
More importantly for the proof of idealism the
psychologistic explication of existence justifies the move of taking sensed
objects (like trees, birds, tables etc.) as nothing apart from their
sensations. Berkeley does not deny that through abstraction we can treat sensed
objects and sensations as different but he points out that this is merely a
semantic difference without being an ontological difference.
VASUBANDHU’S PROOF FOR
IDEALISM
Vasubandhu in the beginning of his Vimsatika presents his proof:
“All this is indeed only consciousness,
because of the appearance (in it)
of non existing objects,
as the vision by the taimirika
of an inexisting net of hairs, etc.”
The Hetu or the middle term here is
‘appearance of non-existing objects’ and the example is people infected with
the disease taimira in which due to the defect of the eye black shadows appear
as hair. The paksha or the minor term is consciousness. The meaning of the
qualifiacation ‘non-existing’ in the hetu is meant to exclude real objects or
mind-independent objects because the existence of objects within consciousness
cannot be regarded as non-existent. The use of the term inexistence or
intentional inexistence to designate the status of the object appearing to
consciousness is misleading because intentionality implies signification to an
external object but from the context we can gather that Vasubandhu is talking
about what appears to consciousness or what itself is an object of
consciousness and hence this object is not intentionally directed to another
outside consciousness. The claim of the object to exist independently of
consciousness is due to the influence of vasanas which as in the dream state
mislead us into thinking that dream objects exist independently of mind. This
is in contrast to Berkeley’s view who sees the error to lie in abstraction of
the two.
Through the method of kevala-vyatireki
Vasubandhu has to show that in every consciousness state there is an appearance
of a non-existent object and in every case where consciousness is absent the
said appearance is also absent. The vyatireki however does not require a
separate proof because it is generally accepted in the Indian tradition. The
positive concomitance is proved by consciousness itself since in no case is the
object of consciousness seen to be independent of consciousness. But Vasubandhu
does not make use of this proof because if dictates of consciousness are to be
followed then consciousness is always seen to be consciousness of something
that itself is not consciousness and it is this that he has to remedy. He has
no reason to intimately tie the together in a way that by very definition an
object of consciousness is inseparable from consciousness. Hence he resorts to
indirect proof or eliminative reasoning by arguing against the very possibility
of a mind-independent real object:
(An external âyatana) cannot be
the object of a cognition
either as one
or as multiple in (isolated) atoms;
neither can these (atoms),
(when they are) conglomerated,
(be object of cognition),
because (in this case) the atom
cannot be proved to exist.
(Vimsatika 11)
Interestingly Vasubandhu does not argue that
consciousness cannot apprehend anything outside itself and hence the object of
consciousness has to enter within the confines of consciousness in order to be
apprehended. The reason seems to be that this does not preclude the possibility
of an external object causing a conscious state with a particular form as an
effect like in the case of Locke or nearer home the Sautrantikas. Hence he
tries to show that the very conception of an external object is imperfect and
hence this defect in the said real object is what precludes its possibility of
being an object of consciousness because of which he tries to prove that ‘the
atom cannot be proved to exist’.
Dignaga’s proof in Alambanapariksha is on the
same grounds but only more sophisticated in its details of argumentation. He
realizes that there is no need to show the impossibility of an external object
being formed out of atoms but only that even if that were correct still such an
object cannot be considered to be the Alambana or support of consciousness:
“Even if the atoms are
the cause of the cognition through the senses,
since (the cognition) does not appear
under the form of those (atoms),
the atoms are not the object of that
(cognition),
in the same way as the sense-organs (are not).”
In order to be considered an object of
consciousness two conditions have to be met: a) it has to be the cause of
cognition b) the form of the cognition has to be the same as the form of the
object that causes the cognition:
“Those who postulate that the support of the
cognition through the eye, etc. is an external thing, consider that either the
atoms are (the cognition's support), because they are its cause, or that a
conglomerate of those (atoms) is (the cognition's support), because there
arises a cognition which appears under the form of that (conglomerate).”
In case of external objects either the atoms
are the cause of the cognition but do not appear in that form or what appears
having a form in a cognition cannot be regarded as the cause since the causes
are the atoms. Hence no external object meets these two conditions
simultaneously. So the conclusion that the object of consciousness is a form or
property of consciousness itself is inseparable.
“The knowable internal form,
which appears as external,
is the object (of the cognition)
because it (=the knowable internal form)
is the form of the cognition
and because it is also its determining
condition” (6 a-d)
Note that the cause is in this case the
‘internal form’ and not vasanas for otherwise the latter theory would also fail
to fulfil the tests for being the object of consciousness just like the
external object. Even though the vasanas are a cause of the internal form it is
the latter that is regarded as the cause of cognition. This however raises
important concerns because the effect has to come after a cause and hence an
external object is regarded as a cause because it pre-exists the effect i.e.
cognition. But in Dignaga’s case the cognition and the internal form appear
simultaneously. So how can the one be regarded as the cause of the other.
Dignaga’s reply in effect is to repudiate the temporality of causation in
favour of necessary dependence which is fulfilled in this case because without
the one the other is not found. Hence simultaneity in causation is not a
problem. Hume would be aghast.
But the superiority of Dignaga’s view can be
seen quite clearly. Simply poking holes in your opponent’s point of view does
not validate your alternative and Vasubandhu gave no reason to believe that the
object of consciousness must be a form of consciousness. Dignaga however did
exactly that – first he formulated a criteria for regarding something as an
object of consciousness and then showed that only the internal form can fulfil
that criteria. Secondly he showed that there is a necessary relation between the
internal form and the cognition since one is never found without other pointing
to a necessary relation between the two which relation is the relation of
causality their simultaneity notwithstanding.
CRITICAL REVIEW OF THE
TWO ARGUMENTS
Even though both sides believe that
consciousness cannot grasp anything not within its own boundaries still the
manner of proof is very difference. In Berkeley what is important is to
establish first the connection between the object of consciousness as such and
the consciousness itself. He proceeds by showing the essential identity of the
two in the case of sensations like pleasure and pain and then showing that the
case of sensed objects like middle-sized objects we encounter in everyday life
are on a par with sensation in this respect. He achieves this through his
separability principle and psychologism. On the other hand Vasubandhu seeks to
show that the very concept of an external object is replete with contradictions
while Dignaga attempts to show that no external object even if it exists can be
the object of consciousness. But while Vasubandhu does not explicitly tell us
about the relation of consciousness and object of consciousness; Dignaga takes
it to be causality even though an instance of simultaneous causality. The
relation is still a necessary one and it is reasonable to believe that the view
is implicitly present even in Vasubandhu because of his theory of vasanas. That
the actualization of a vasana would demand an appeal to the law of karma is a
different issue but most philosophical traditions in India believe the physical
and the mental to be subordinate to the moral dimension of the world – even in
case of an atheistic religion like Buddhism.
We can assess the strength of the two
arguments by comparing their response to Trendelenburg’s Neglected alternative
objection. This object was originally raised by Trendelenburg against Kant. He
argued that even if we grant that space and time are a-priori intuitions of
sensibility and appearances owe their spatial and temporal form to this
constitution of the human mind even then is it still not possible that things
in themselves are still spatially and temporally ordered? Why do they have to
lack that order and why cannot spatial and temporal notions be not applied to
things in themselves?
Kant and Berkeley both can escape this
objection through their psychologism. Considering Berkeley in particular he
regarded space and time to be abstract ideas and hence nothing more than
representations and hence cannot be ascribed to external objects that
themselves are not representations. But he never denied that there cannot be a
‘third nature’ (Dialogue Between Hylas and Philonaus 3D239) which can exist
independently of the human mind provided we keep in mind the separability
principle and the restriction on the application of mental concepts to
non-mental reality. As he clarifies:
“I do not deny the existence of material
substance, merely because I have no notion of it, but because the notion of it
is inconsistent, or in other words because it is repugnant that there should be
a notion of it. Many things, for ought I know, may exist, whereof neither I nor
any other man hath or can have any idea or notion whatsoever. But then those
things must be possible, that is, nothing inconsistent must be included in
their definition”
The ‘third nature’ even if it can exist would
mean nothing to me because the source or origin of meaning lies in sensation
and the existence in sensation as we have seen is inseparable from the
sensation itself because the two are identical.
Coming to Vasubandhu I cannot see what
response he can give to Trendelenburg except by criticizing his notion of an
external object. But then we have no reason why an external object cannot be
different from the manner of conception usually found in the schools of thought
prevalent in Vasubandhu’s time and why a form cannot both be a property of a
consciousness and also a distinct external existence. Dignaga too does not fair
better in this case because as is well known he has no way to ground modal
notions like necessity in the framework of his empiricist logic. As a Humean would
naturally retort if the object of consciousness and consciousness itself are
different then there is no reason to deny why one cannot be found without the
other even if they appear simultaneously. On the other hand if he regards them
as identical then no causal relation between the two is possible just as a
mountain cannot be regarded as the cause of a valley – distinct existence is
need for a causal relation to exist. But then Dignaga has pointed out no reason
to regard the two as identical especially since simultaneity does not entail
identity. This then shows the greater superiority of Berkeley’s proof since he
can argue for identity given his separability principle he has reason to
tighten the connection between the existence in consciousness and the consciousness
of that existence by showing that the two can be separated in thought but not
in reality. Locke believes that the sensed object has a resemblance to an
external object it is possible that it is identical with sensation and yet
there be a resembling external object outside the sensation. He also argues for
the identity of the sensed object and sensation on external grounds. But
Berkeley made it possible to assert the identity of the two on internal
grounds. In his case the inseparability and consequent identity of the two is
established by consciousness itself because we never perceive an object of
consciousness independently of consciousness and this test of kevala and
vyatirekin i.e. agreement in presence and in absence warrants the relation between
the two to be regarded as an identity since through his separability principle
he shows that the two are separable only in thought but not in reality. The
identity of the two is established thereby by the testimony of consciousness;
their semantic distinction notwithstanding since it can be shown to be bereft
of ontological significance thanks to the separability principle.
-x-x-x-x-x-x-x-x-x-x-x-x-x-x-x-x-x-x-x-x-x-x-
Comments
Post a Comment